EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION.
RIGHTS OF MAN. PART THE FIRST.
RIGHTS OF MAN. PART SECOND, COMBINING PRINCIPLE AND PRACTICE.
INTRODUCTION.
CHAPTER I. OF SOCIETY AND CIVILISATION
CHAPTER II. OF THE ORIGIN OF THE PRESENT OLD GOVERNMENTS
CHAPTER III. OF THE OLD AND NEW SYSTEMS OF GOVERNMENT
CHAPTER IV. OF CONSTITUTIONS
CHAPTER V. WAYS AND MEANS OF IMPROVING THE CONDITION OF EUROPE
EDITOR'S INTRODUCTION.
WHEN
Thomas Paine sailed from America for France, in April, 1787, he was
perhaps as happy a man as any in the world. His most intimate friend,
Jefferson, was Minister at Paris, and his friend Lafayette was the
idol of France. His fame had preceded him, and he at once became, in
Paris, the centre of the same circle of savants and philosophers that
had surrounded Franklin. His main reason for proceeding at once to
Paris was that he might submit to the Academy of Sciences his
invention of an iron bridge, and with its favorable verdict he came
to England, in September. He at once went to his aged mother at
Thetford, leaving with a publisher (Ridgway), his "Prospects on
the Rubicon." He next made arrangements to patent his bridge,
and to construct at Rotherham the large model of it exhibited on
Paddington Green, London. He was welcomed in England by leading
statesmen, such as Lansdowne and Fox, and above all by Edmund Burke,
who for some time had him as a guest at Beaconsfield, and drove him
about in various parts of the country. He had not the slightest
revolutionary purpose, either as regarded England or France. Towards
Louis XVI. he felt only gratitude for the services he had rendered
America, and towards George III. he felt no animosity whatever. His
four months' sojourn in Paris had convinced him that there was
approaching a reform of that country after the American model, except
that the Crown would be preserved, a compromise he approved, provided
the throne should not be hereditary. Events in France travelled more
swiftly than he had anticipated, and Paine was summoned by Lafayette,
Condorcet, and others, as an adviser in the formation of a new
constitution.Such
was the situation immediately preceding the political and literary
duel between Paine and Burke, which in the event turned out a
tremendous war between Royalism and Republicanism in Europe. Paine
was, both in France and in England, the inspirer of moderate
counsels. Samuel Rogers relates that in early life he dined at a
friend's house in London with Thomas Paine, when one of the toasts
given was the "memory of Joshua,"—in allusion to the
Hebrew leader's conquest of the kings of Canaan, and execution of
them. Paine observed that he would not treat kings like Joshua. "I
'm of the Scotch parson's opinion," he said, "when he
prayed against Louis XIV.—`Lord, shake him over the mouth of hell,
but don't let him drop!'" Paine then gave as his toast, "The
Republic of the World,"—which Samuel Rogers, aged twenty-nine,
noted as a sublime idea. This was Paine's faith and hope, and with it
he confronted the revolutionary storms which presently burst over
France and England.Until
Burke's arraignment of France in his parliamentary speech (February
9, 1790), Paine had no doubt whatever that he would sympathize with
the movement in France, and wrote to him from that country as if
conveying glad tidings. Burke's "Reflections on the Revolution
in France" appeared November 1, 1790, and Paine at once set
himself to answer it. He was then staying at the Angel Inn,
Islington. The inn has been twice rebuilt since that time, and from
its contents there is preserved only a small image, which perhaps was
meant to represent "Liberty,"—possibly brought from Paris
by Paine as an ornament for his study. From the Angel he removed to a
house in Harding Street, Fetter Lane. Rickman says Part First of
"Rights of Man" was finished at Versailles, but probably
this has reference to the preface only, as I cannot find Paine in
France that year until April 8. The book had been printed by Johnson,
in time for the opening of Parliament, in February; but this
publisher became frightened after a few copies were out (there is one
in the British Museum), and the work was transferred to J. S. Jordan,
166 Fleet Street, with a preface sent from Paris (not contained in
Johnson's edition, nor in the American editions). The pamphlet,
though sold at the same price as Burke's, three shillings, had a vast
circulation, and Paine gave the proceeds to the Constitutional
Societies which sprang up under his teachings in various parts of the
country.Soon
after appeared Burke's "Appeal from the New to the Old Whigs."
In this Burke quoted a good deal from "Rights of Man," but
replied to it only with exclamation points, saying that the only
answer such ideas merited was "criminal justice." Paine's
Part Second followed, published February 17, 1792. In Part First
Paine had mentioned a rumor that Burke was a masked pensioner (a
charge that will be noticed in connection with its detailed statement
in a further publication); and as Burke had been formerly arraigned
in Parliament, while Paymaster, for a very questionable proceeding,
this charge no doubt hurt a good deal. Although the government did
not follow Burke's suggestion of a prosecution at that time, there is
little doubt that it was he who induced the prosecution of Part
Second. Before the trial came on, December 18, 1792, Paine was
occupying his seat in the French Convention, and could only be
outlawed.Burke
humorously remarked to a friend of Paine and himself, "We hunt
in pairs." The severally representative character and influence
of these two men in the revolutionary era, in France and England,
deserve more adequate study than they have received. While Paine
maintained freedom of discussion, Burke first proposed criminal
prosecution for sentiments by no means libellous (such as Paine's
Part First). While Paine was endeavoring to make the movement in
France peaceful, Burke fomented the league of monarchs against France
which maddened its people, and brought on the Reign of Terror. While
Paine was endeavoring to preserve the French throne ("phantom"
though he believed it), to prevent bloodshed, Burke was secretly
writing to the Queen of France, entreating her not to compromise, and
to "trust to the support of foreign armies" ("Histoire
de France depuis 1789." Henri Martin, i., 151). While Burke thus
helped to bring the King and Queen to the guillotine, Paine pleaded
for their lives to the last moment. While Paine maintained the right
of mankind to improve their condition, Burke held that "the
awful Author of our being is the author of our place in the order of
existence; and that, having disposed and marshalled us by a divine
tactick, not according to our will, but according to his, he has, in
and by that disposition, virtually subjected us to act the part which
belongs to the place assigned us." Paine was a religious
believer in eternal principles; Burke held that "political
problems do not primarily concern truth or falsehood. They relate to
good or evil. What in the result is likely to produce evil is
politically false, that which is productive of good politically is
true." Assuming thus the visionary's right to decide before the
result what was "likely to produce evil," Burke vigorously
sought to kindle war against the French Republic which might have
developed itself peacefully, while Paine was striving for an
international Congress in Europe in the interest of peace. Paine had
faith in the people, and believed that, if allowed to choose
representatives, they would select their best and wisest men; and
that while reforming government the people would remain orderly, as
they had generally remained in America during the transition from
British rule to selfgovernment. Burke maintained that if the existing
political order were broken up there would be no longer a people, but
"a number of vague, loose individuals, and nothing more."
"Alas!" he exclaims, "they little know how many a
weary step is to be taken before they can form themselves into a
mass, which has a true personality." For the sake of peace Paine
wished the revolution to be peaceful as the advance of summer; he
used every endeavor to reconcile English radicals to some modus
vivendi with the existing order, as he was willing to retain Louis
XVI. as head of the executive in France: Burke resisted every
tendency of English statesmanship to reform at home, or to negotiate
with the French Republic, and was mainly responsible for the King's
death and the war that followed between England and France in
February, 1793. Burke became a royal favorite, Paine was outlawed by
a prosecution originally proposed by Burke. While Paine was demanding
religious liberty, Burke was opposing the removal of penal statutes
from Unitarians, on the ground that but for those statutes Paine
might some day set up a church in England. When Burke was retiring on
a large royal pension, Paine was in prison, through the devices of
Burke's confederate, the American Minister in Paris. So the two men,
as Burke said, "hunted in pairs."So
far as Burke attempts to affirm any principle he is fairly quoted in
Paine's work, and nowhere misrepresented. As for Paine's own ideas,
the reader should remember that "Rights of Man" was the
earliest complete statement of republican principles. They were
pronounced to be the fundamental principles of the American Republic
by Jefferson, Madison, and Jackson,-the three Presidents who above
all others represented the republican idea which Paine first allied
with American Independence. Those who suppose that Paine did but
reproduce the principles of Rousseau and Locke will find by careful
study of his well-weighed language that such is not the case. Paine's
political principles were evolved out of his early Quakerism. He was
potential in George Fox. The belief that every human soul was the
child of God, and capable of direct inspiration from the Father of
all, without mediator or priestly intervention, or sacramental
instrumentality, was fatal to all privilege and rank. The universal
Fatherhood implied universal Brotherhood, or human equality. But the
fate of the Quakers proved the necessity of protecting the individual
spirit from oppression by the majority as well as by privileged
classes. For this purpose Paine insisted on surrounding the
individual right with the security of the Declaration of Rights, not
to be invaded by any government; and would reduce government to an
association limited in its operations to the defence of those rights
which the individual is unable, alone, to maintain.From
the preceding chapter it will be seen that Part Second of "Rights
of Man" was begun by Paine in the spring of 1791. At the close
of that year, or early in 1792, he took up his abode with his friend
Thomas "Clio" Rickman, at No. 7 Upper Marylebone Street.
Rickman was a radical publisher; the house remains still a
book-binding establishment, and seems little changed since Paine
therein revised the proofs of Part Second on a table which Rickman
marked with a plate, and which is now in possession of Mr. Edward
Truelove. As the plate states, Paine wrote on the same table other
works which appeared in England in 1792.In
1795 D. I. Eaton published an edition of "Rights of Man,"
with a preface purporting to have been written by Paine while in
Luxembourg prison. It is manifestly spurious. The genuine English and
French prefaces are given.
RIGHTS OF MAN. PART THE FIRST.
BEING AN ANSWER TO MR. BURKE'S
ATTACK ON THE FRENCH REVOLUTION
Among the incivilities by which nations or individuals provoke and
irritate each other, Mr. Burke's pamphlet on the French Revolution
is an extraordinary instance. Neither the People of France, nor the
National Assembly, were troubling themselves about the affairs of
England, or the English Parliament; and that Mr. Burke should
commence an unprovoked attack upon them, both in Parliament and in
public, is a conduct that cannot be pardoned on the score of
manners, nor justified on that of policy.There is scarcely an epithet of abuse to be found in the
English language, with which Mr. Burke has not loaded the French
Nation and the National Assembly. Everything which rancour,
prejudice, ignorance or knowledge could suggest, is poured forth in
the copious fury of near four hundred pages. In the strain and on
the plan Mr. Burke was writing, he might have written on to as many
thousands. When the tongue or the pen is let loose in a frenzy of
passion, it is the man, and not the subject, that becomes
exhausted.Hitherto Mr. Burke has been mistaken and disappointed in the
opinions he had formed of the affairs of France; but such is the
ingenuity of his hope, or the malignancy of his despair, that it
furnishes him with new pretences to go on. There was a time when it
was impossible to make Mr. Burke believe there would be any
Revolution in France. His opinion then was, that the French had
neither spirit to undertake it nor fortitude to support it; and now
that there is one, he seeks an escape by condemning it.Not sufficiently content with abusing the National Assembly,
a great part of his work is taken up with abusing Dr. Price (one of
the best-hearted men that lives) and the two societies in England
known by the name of the Revolution Society and the Society for
Constitutional Information.Dr. Price had preached a sermon on the 4th of November, 1789,
being the anniversary of what is called in England the Revolution,
which took place 1688. Mr. Burke, speaking of this sermon, says:
"The political Divine proceeds dogmatically to assert, that by the
principles of the Revolution, the people of England have acquired
three fundamental rights:1. To choose our own governors.2. To cashier them for misconduct.3. To frame a government for ourselves."Dr. Price does not say that the right to do these things
exists in this or in that person, or in this or in that description
of persons, but that it exists in the whole; that it is a right
resident in the nation. Mr. Burke, on the contrary, denies that
such a right exists in the nation, either in whole or in part, or
that it exists anywhere; and, what is still more strange and
marvellous, he says: "that the people of England utterly disclaim
such a right, and that they will resist the practical assertion of
it with their lives and fortunes." That men should take up arms and
spend their lives and fortunes, not to maintain their rights, but
to maintain they have not rights, is an entirely new species of
discovery, and suited to the paradoxical genius of Mr.
Burke.The method which Mr. Burke takes to prove that the people of
England have no such rights, and that such rights do not now exist
in the nation, either in whole or in part, or anywhere at all, is
of the same marvellous and monstrous kind with what he has already
said; for his arguments are that the persons, or the generation of
persons, in whom they did exist, are dead, and with them the right
is dead also. To prove this, he quotes a declaration made by
Parliament about a hundred years ago, to William and Mary, in these
words: "The Lords Spiritual and Temporal, and Commons, do, in the
name of the people aforesaid" (meaning the people of England then
living) "most humbly and faithfully submit themselves, their heirs
and posterities, for Ever." He quotes a clause of another Act of
Parliament made in the same reign, the terms of which he says,
"bind us" (meaning the people of their day), "our heirs and our
posterity, to them, their heirs and posterity, to the end of
time."Mr. Burke conceives his point sufficiently established by
producing those clauses, which he enforces by saying that they
exclude the right of the nation for ever. And not yet content with
making such declarations, repeated over and over again, he farther
says, "that if the people of England possessed such a right before
the Revolution" (which he acknowledges to have been the case, not
only in England, but throughout Europe, at an early period), "yet
that the English Nation did, at the time of the Revolution, most
solemnly renounce and abdicate it, for themselves, and for all
their posterity, for ever."As Mr. Burke occasionally applies the poison drawn from his
horrid principles, not only to the English nation, but to the
French Revolution and the National Assembly, and charges that
august, illuminated and illuminating body of men with the epithet
of usurpers, I shall, sans ceremonie, place another system of
principles in opposition to his.The English Parliament of 1688 did a certain thing, which,
for themselves and their constituents, they had a right to do, and
which it appeared right should be done. But, in addition to this
right, which they possessed by delegation, they set up another
right by assumption, that of binding and controlling posterity to
the end of time. The case, therefore, divides itself into two
parts; the right which they possessed by delegation, and the right
which they set up by assumption. The first is admitted; but with
respect to the second, I reply: There never did, there never will,
and there never can, exist a Parliament, or any description of men,
or any generation of men, in any country, possessed of the right or
the power of binding and controlling posterity to the "end of
time," or of commanding for ever how the world shall be governed,
or who shall govern it; and therefore all such clauses, acts or
declarations by which the makers of them attempt to do what they
have neither the right nor the power to do, nor the power to
execute, are in themselves null and void. Every age and generation
must be as free to act for itself in all cases as the age and
generations which preceded it. The vanity and presumption of
governing beyond the grave is the most ridiculous and insolent of
all tyrannies. Man has no property in man; neither has any
generation a property in the generations which are to follow. The
Parliament or the people of 1688, or of any other period, had no
more right to dispose of the people of the present day, or to bind
or to control them in any shape whatever, than the parliament or
the people of the present day have to dispose of, bind or control
those who are to live a hundred or a thousand years hence. Every
generation is, and must be, competent to all the purposes which its
occasions require. It is the living, and not the dead, that are to
be accommodated. When man ceases to be, his power and his wants
cease with him; and having no longer any participation in the
concerns of this world, he has no longer any authority in directing
who shall be its governors, or how its government shall be
organised, or how administered.I am not contending for nor against any form of government,
nor for nor against any party, here or elsewhere. That which a
whole nation chooses to do it has a right to do. Mr. Burke says,
No. Where, then, does the right exist? I am contending for the
rights of the living, and against their being willed away and
controlled and contracted for by the manuscript assumed authority
of the dead, and Mr. Burke is contending for the authority of the
dead over the rights and freedom of the living. There was a time
when kings disposed of their crowns by will upon their death-beds,
and consigned the people, like beasts of the field, to whatever
successor they appointed. This is now so exploded as scarcely to be
remembered, and so monstrous as hardly to be believed. But the
Parliamentary clauses upon which Mr. Burke builds his political
church are of the same nature.The laws of every country must be analogous to some common
principle. In England no parent or master, nor all the authority of
Parliament, omnipotent as it has called itself, can bind or control
the personal freedom even of an individual beyond the age of
twenty-one years. On what ground of right, then, could the
Parliament of 1688, or any other Parliament, bind all posterity for
ever?Those who have quitted the world, and those who have not yet
arrived at it, are as remote from each other as the utmost stretch
of mortal imagination can conceive. What possible obligation, then,
can exist between them—what rule or principle can be laid down that
of two nonentities, the one out of existence and the other not in,
and who never can meet in this world, the one should control the
other to the end of time?In England it is said that money cannot be taken out of the
pockets of the people without their consent. But who authorised, or
who could authorise, the Parliament of 1688 to control and take
away the freedom of posterity (who were not in existence to give or
to withhold their consent) and limit and confine their right of
acting in certain cases for ever?A greater absurdity cannot present itself to the
understanding of man than what Mr. Burke offers to his readers. He
tells them, and he tells the world to come, that a certain body of
men who existed a hundred years ago made a law, and that there does
not exist in the nation, nor ever will, nor ever can, a power to
alter it. Under how many subtilties or absurdities has the divine
right to govern been imposed on the credulity of mankind? Mr. Burke
has discovered a new one, and he has shortened his journey to Rome
by appealing to the power of this infallible Parliament of former
days, and he produces what it has done as of divine authority, for
that power must certainly be more than human which no human power
to the end of time can alter.But Mr. Burke has done some service—not to his cause, but to
his country—by bringing those clauses into public view. They serve
to demonstrate how necessary it is at all times to watch against
the attempted encroachment of power, and to prevent its running to
excess. It is somewhat extraordinary that the offence for which
James II. was expelled, that of setting up power by assumption,
should be re-acted, under another shape and form, by the Parliament
that expelled him. It shows that the Rights of Man were but
imperfectly understood at the Revolution, for certain it is that
the right which that Parliament set up by assumption (for by the
delegation it had not, and could not have it, because none could
give it) over the persons and freedom of posterity for ever was of
the same tyrannical unfounded kind which James attempted to set up
over the Parliament and the nation, and for which he was expelled.
The only difference is (for in principle they differ not) that the
one was an usurper over living, and the other over the unborn; and
as the one has no better authority to stand upon than the other,
both of them must be equally null and void, and of no
effect.From what, or from whence, does Mr. Burke prove the right of
any human power to bind posterity for ever? He has produced his
clauses, but he must produce also his proofs that such a right
existed, and show how it existed. If it ever existed it must now
exist, for whatever appertains to the nature of man cannot be
annihilated by man. It is the nature of man to die, and he will
continue to die as long as he continues to be born. But Mr. Burke
has set up a sort of political Adam, in whom all posterity are
bound for ever. He must, therefore, prove that his Adam possessed
such a power, or such a right.The weaker any cord is, the less will it bear to be
stretched, and the worse is the policy to stretch it, unless it is
intended to break it. Had anyone proposed the overthrow of Mr.
Burke's positions, he would have proceeded as Mr. Burke has done.
He would have magnified the authorities, on purpose to have called
the right of them into question; and the instant the question of
right was started, the authorities must have been given
up.It requires but a very small glance of thought to perceive
that although laws made in one generation often continue in force
through succeeding generations, yet they continue to derive their
force from the consent of the living. A law not repealed continues
in force, not because it cannot be repealed, but because it is not
repealed; and the non-repealing passes for consent.But Mr. Burke's clauses have not even this qualification in
their favour. They become null, by attempting to become immortal.
The nature of them precludes consent. They destroy the right which
they might have, by grounding it on a right which they cannot have.
Immortal power is not a human right, and therefore cannot be a
right of Parliament. The Parliament of 1688 might as well have
passed an act to have authorised themselves to live for ever, as to
make their authority live for ever. All, therefore, that can be
said of those clauses is that they are a formality of words, of as
much import as if those who used them had addressed a
congratulation to themselves, and in the oriental style of
antiquity had said: O Parliament, live for ever!The circumstances of the world are continually changing, and
the opinions of men change also; and as government is for the
living, and not for the dead, it is the living only that has any
right in it. That which may be thought right and found convenient
in one age may be thought wrong and found inconvenient in another.
In such cases, who is to decide, the living or the dead?As almost one hundred pages of Mr. Burke's book are employed
upon these clauses, it will consequently follow that if the clauses
themselves, so far as they set up an assumed usurped dominion over
posterity for ever, are unauthoritative, and in their nature null
and void; that all his voluminous inferences, and declamation drawn
therefrom, or founded thereon, are null and void also; and on this
ground I rest the matter.We now come more particularly to the affairs of France. Mr.
Burke's book has the appearance of being written as instruction to
the French nation; but if I may permit myself the use of an
extravagant metaphor, suited to the extravagance of the case, it is
darkness attempting to illuminate light.While I am writing this there are accidentally before me some
proposals for a declaration of rights by the Marquis de la Fayette
(I ask his pardon for using his former address, and do it only for
distinction's sake) to the National Assembly, on the 11th of July,
1789, three days before the taking of the Bastille, and I cannot
but remark with astonishment how opposite the sources are from
which that gentleman and Mr. Burke draw their principles. Instead
of referring to musty records and mouldy parchments to prove that
the rights of the living are lost, "renounced and abdicated for
ever," by those who are now no more, as Mr. Burke has done, M. de
la Fayette applies to the living world, and emphatically says:
"Call to mind the sentiments which nature has engraved on the heart
of every citizen, and which take a new force when they are solemnly
recognised by all:—For a nation to love liberty, it is sufficient
that she knows it; and to be free, it is sufficient that she wills
it." How dry, barren, and obscure is the source from which Mr.
Burke labors! and how ineffectual, though gay with flowers, are all
his declamation and his arguments compared with these clear,
concise, and soul-animating sentiments! Few and short as they are,
they lead on to a vast field of generous and manly thinking, and do
not finish, like Mr. Burke's periods, with music in the ear, and
nothing in the heart.As I have introduced M. de la Fayette, I will take the
liberty of adding an anecdote respecting his farewell address to
the Congress of America in 1783, and which occurred fresh to my
mind, when I saw Mr. Burke's thundering attack on the French
Revolution. M. de la Fayette went to America at the early period of
the war, and continued a volunteer in her service to the end. His
conduct through the whole of that enterprise is one of the most
extraordinary that is to be found in the history of a young man,
scarcely twenty years of age. Situated in a country that was like
the lap of sensual pleasure, and with the means of enjoying it, how
few are there to be found who would exchange such a scene for the
woods and wildernesses of America, and pass the flowery years of
youth in unprofitable danger and hardship! but such is the fact.
When the war ended, and he was on the point of taking his final
departure, he presented himself to Congress, and contemplating in
his affectionate farewell the Revolution he had seen, expressed
himself in these words: "May this great monument raised to liberty
serve as a lesson to the oppressor, and an example to the
oppressed!" When this address came to the hands of Dr. Franklin,
who was then in France, he applied to Count Vergennes to have it
inserted in the French Gazette, but never could obtain his consent.
The fact was that Count Vergennes was an aristocratical despot at
home, and dreaded the example of the American Revolution in France,
as certain other persons now dread the example of the French
Revolution in England, and Mr. Burke's tribute of fear (for in this
light his book must be considered) runs parallel with Count
Vergennes' refusal. But to return more particularly to his
work."We have seen," says Mr. Burke, "the French rebel against a
mild and lawful monarch, with more fury, outrage, and insult, than
any people has been known to rise against the most illegal usurper,
or the most sanguinary tyrant." This is one among a thousand other
instances, in which Mr. Burke shows that he is ignorant of the
springs and principles of the French Revolution.It was not against Louis XVI. but against the despotic
principles of the Government, that the nation revolted. These
principles had not their origin in him, but in the original
establishment, many centuries back: and they were become too deeply
rooted to be removed, and the Augean stables of parasites and
plunderers too abominably filthy to be cleansed by anything short
of a complete and universal Revolution. When it becomes necessary
to do anything, the whole heart and soul should go into the
measure, or not attempt it. That crisis was then arrived, and there
remained no choice but to act with determined vigor, or not to act
at all. The king was known to be the friend of the nation, and this
circumstance was favorable to the enterprise. Perhaps no man bred
up in the style of an absolute king, ever possessed a heart so
little disposed to the exercise of that species of power as the
present King of France. But the principles of the Government itself
still remained the same. The Monarch and the Monarchy were distinct
and separate things; and it was against the established despotism
of the latter, and not against the person or principles of the
former, that the revolt commenced, and the Revolution has been
carried.Mr. Burke does not attend to the distinction between men and
principles, and, therefore, he does not see that a revolt may take
place against the despotism of the latter, while there lies no
charge of despotism against the former.The natural moderation of Louis XVI. contributed nothing to
alter the hereditary despotism of the monarchy. All the tyrannies
of former reigns, acted under that hereditary despotism, were still
liable to be revived in the hands of a successor. It was not the
respite of a reign that would satisfy France, enlightened as she
was then become. A casual discontinuance of the practice of
despotism, is not a discontinuance of its principles: the former
depends on the virtue of the individual who is in immediate
possession of the power; the latter, on the virtue and fortitude of
the nation. In the case of Charles I. and James II. of England, the
revolt was against the personal despotism of the men; whereas in
France, it was against the hereditary despotism of the established
Government. But men who can consign over the rights of posterity
for ever on the authority of a mouldy parchment, like Mr. Burke,
are not qualified to judge of this Revolution. It takes in a field
too vast for their views to explore, and proceeds with a mightiness
of reason they cannot keep pace with.But there are many points of view in which this Revolution
may be considered. When despotism has established itself for ages
in a country, as in France, it is not in the person of the king
only that it resides. It has the appearance of being so in show,
and in nominal authority; but it is not so in practice and in fact.
It has its standard everywhere. Every office and department has its
despotism, founded upon custom and usage. Every place has its
Bastille, and every Bastille its despot. The original hereditary
despotism resident in the person of the king, divides and
sub-divides itself into a thousand shapes and forms, till at last
the whole of it is acted by deputation. This was the case in
France; and against this species of despotism, proceeding on
through an endless labyrinth of office till the source of it is
scarcely perceptible, there is no mode of redress. It strengthens
itself by assuming the appearance of duty, and tyrannies under the
pretence of obeying.When a man reflects on the condition which France was in from
the nature of her government, he will see other causes for revolt
than those which immediately connect themselves with the person or
character of Louis XVI. There were, if I may so express it, a
thousand despotisms to be reformed in France, which had grown up
under the hereditary despotism of the monarchy, and became so
rooted as to be in a great measure independent of it. Between the
Monarchy, the Parliament, and the Church there was a rivalship of
despotism; besides the feudal despotism operating locally, and the
ministerial despotism operating everywhere. But Mr. Burke, by
considering the king as the only possible object of a revolt,
speaks as if France was a village, in which everything that passed
must be known to its commanding officer, and no oppression could be
acted but what he could immediately control. Mr. Burke might have
been in the Bastille his whole life, as well under Louis XVI. as
Louis XIV., and neither the one nor the other have known that such
a man as Burke existed. The despotic principles of the government
were the same in both reigns, though the dispositions of the men
were as remote as tyranny and benevolence.What Mr. Burke considers as a reproach to the French
Revolution (that of bringing it forward under a reign more mild
than the preceding ones) is one of its highest honors. The
Revolutions that have taken place in other European countries, have
been excited by personal hatred. The rage was against the man, and
he became the victim. But, in the instance of France we see a
Revolution generated in the rational contemplation of the Rights of
Man, and distinguishing from the beginning between persons and
principles.But Mr. Burke appears to have no idea of principles when he
is contemplating Governments. "Ten years ago," says he, "I could
have felicitated France on her having a Government, without
inquiring what the nature of that Government was, or how it was
administered." Is this the language of a rational man? Is it the
language of a heart feeling as it ought to feel for the rights and
happiness of the human race? On this ground, Mr. Burke must
compliment all the Governments in the world, while the victims who
suffer under them, whether sold into slavery, or tortured out of
existence, are wholly forgotten. It is power, and not principles,
that Mr. Burke venerates; and under this abominable depravity he is
disqualified to judge between them. Thus much for his opinion as to
the occasions of the French Revolution. I now proceed to other
considerations.I know a place in America called Point-no-Point, because as
you proceed along the shore, gay and flowery as Mr. Burke's
language, it continually recedes and presents itself at a distance
before you; but when you have got as far as you can go, there is no
point at all. Just thus it is with Mr. Burke's three hundred and
sixty-six pages. It is therefore difficult to reply to him. But as
the points he wishes to establish may be inferred from what he
abuses, it is in his paradoxes that we must look for his
arguments.As to the tragic paintings by which Mr. Burke has outraged
his own imagination, and seeks to work upon that of his readers,
they are very well calculated for theatrical representation, where
facts are manufactured for the sake of show, and accommodated to
produce, through the weakness of sympathy, a weeping effect. But
Mr. Burke should recollect that he is writing history, and not
plays, and that his readers will expect truth, and not the spouting
rant of high-toned exclamation.When we see a man dramatically lamenting in a publication
intended to be believed that "The age of chivalry is gone! that The
glory of Europe is extinguished for ever! that The unbought grace
of life (if anyone knows what it is), the cheap defence of nations,
the nurse of manly sentiment and heroic enterprise is gone!" and
all this because the Quixot age of chivalry nonsense is gone, what
opinion can we form of his judgment, or what regard can we pay to
his facts? In the rhapsody of his imagination he has discovered a
world of wind mills, and his sorrows are that there are no Quixots
to attack them. But if the age of aristocracy, like that of
chivalry, should fall (and they had originally some connection) Mr.
Burke, the trumpeter of the Order, may continue his parody to the
end, and finish with exclaiming: "Othello's occupation's
gone!"Notwithstanding Mr. Burke's horrid paintings, when the French
Revolution is compared with the Revolutions of other countries, the
astonishment will be that it is marked with so few sacrifices; but
this astonishment will cease when we reflect that principles, and
not persons, were the meditated objects of destruction. The mind of
the nation was acted upon by a higher stimulus than what the
consideration of persons could inspire, and sought a higher
conquest than could be produced by the downfall of an enemy. Among
the few who fell there do not appear to be any that were
intentionally singled out. They all of them had their fate in the
circumstances of the moment, and were not pursued with that long,
cold-blooded unabated revenge which pursued the unfortunate Scotch
in the affair of 1745.Through the whole of Mr. Burke's book I do not observe that
the Bastille is mentioned more than once, and that with a kind of
implication as if he were sorry it was pulled down, and wished it
were built up again. "We have rebuilt Newgate," says he, "and
tenanted the mansion; and we have prisons almost as strong as the
Bastille for those who dare to libel the queens of France."*2As to what a madman like the
person called Lord George Gordon might say, and to whom Newgate is
rather a bedlam than a prison, it is unworthy a rational
consideration. It was a madman that libelled, and that is
sufficient apology; and it afforded an opportunity for confining
him, which was the thing that was wished for. But certain it is
that Mr. Burke, who does not call himself a madman (whatever other
people may do), has libelled in the most unprovoked manner, and in
the grossest style of the most vulgar abuse, the whole
representative authority of France, and yet Mr. Burke takes his
seat in the British House of Commons! From his violence and his
grief, his silence on some points and his excess on others, it is
difficult not to believe that Mr. Burke is sorry, extremely sorry,
that arbitrary power, the power of the Pope and the Bastille, are
pulled down.Not one glance of compassion, not one commiserating
reflection that I can find throughout his book, has he bestowed on
those who lingered out the most wretched of lives, a life without
hope in the most miserable of prisons. It is painful to behold a
man employing his talents to corrupt himself. Nature has been
kinder to Mr. Burke than he is to her. He is not affected by the
reality of distress touching his heart, but by the showy
resemblance of it striking his imagination. He pities the plumage,
but forgets the dying bird. Accustomed to kiss the aristocratical
hand that hath purloined him from himself, he degenerates into a
composition of art, and the genuine soul of nature forsakes him.
His hero or his heroine must be a tragedy-victim expiring in show,
and not the real prisoner of misery, sliding into death in the
silence of a dungeon.As Mr. Burke has passed over the whole transaction of the
Bastille (and his silence is nothing in his favour), and has
entertained his readers with refections on supposed facts distorted
into real falsehoods, I will give, since he has not, some account
of the circumstances which preceded that transaction. They will
serve to show that less mischief could scarcely have accompanied
such an event when considered with the treacherous and hostile
aggravations of the enemies of the Revolution.The mind can hardly picture to itself a more tremendous scene
than what the city of Paris exhibited at the time of taking the
Bastille, and for two days before and after, nor perceive the
possibility of its quieting so soon. At a distance this transaction
has appeared only as an act of heroism standing on itself, and the
close political connection it had with the Revolution is lost in
the brilliancy of the achievement. But we are to consider it as the
strength of the parties brought man to man, and contending for the
issue. The Bastille was to be either the prize or the prison of the
assailants. The downfall of it included the idea of the downfall of
despotism, and this compounded image was become as figuratively
united as Bunyan's Doubting Castle and Giant Despair.The National Assembly, before and at the time of taking the
Bastille, was sitting at Versailles, twelve miles distant from
Paris. About a week before the rising of the Partisans, and their
taking the Bastille, it was discovered that a plot was forming, at
the head of which was the Count D'Artois, the king's youngest
brother, for demolishing the National Assembly, seizing its
members, and thereby crushing, by a coup de main, all hopes and
prospects of forming a free government. For the sake of humanity,
as well as freedom, it is well this plan did not succeed. Examples
are not wanting to show how dreadfully vindictive and cruel are all
old governments, when they are successful against what they call a
revolt.This plan must have been some time in contemplation; because,
in order to carry it into execution, it was necessary to collect a
large military force round Paris, and cut off the communication
between that city and the National Assembly at Versailles. The
troops destined for this service were chiefly the foreign troops in
the pay of France, and who, for this particular purpose, were drawn
from the distant provinces where they were then stationed. When
they were collected to the amount of between twenty-five and thirty
[...]