INTRODUCTION AND ANALYSIS.
Section 1.
Section 2.
Section 3.
Section 4.
Section 5.
Section 6.
Section 7.
Section 8.
TIMAEUS.
INTRODUCTION AND ANALYSIS.
Of
all the writings of Plato the Timaeus is the most obscure and
repulsive to the modern reader, and has nevertheless had the greatest
influence over the ancient and mediaeval world. The obscurity arises
in the infancy of physical science, out of the confusion of
theological, mathematical, and physiological notions, out of the
desire to conceive the whole of nature without any adequate knowledge
of the parts, and from a greater perception of similarities which lie
on the surface than of differences which are hidden from view. To
bring sense under the control of reason; to find some way through the
mist or labyrinth of appearances, either the highway of mathematics,
or more devious paths suggested by the analogy of man with the world,
and of the world with man; to see that all things have a cause and
are tending towards an end—this is the spirit of the ancient
physical philosopher. He has no notion of trying an experiment and is
hardly capable of observing the curiosities of nature which are
'tumbling out at his feet,' or of interpreting even the most obvious
of them. He is driven back from the nearer to the more distant, from
particulars to generalities, from the earth to the stars. He lifts up
his eyes to the heavens and seeks to guide by their motions his
erring footsteps. But we neither appreciate the conditions of
knowledge to which he was subjected, nor have the ideas which
fastened upon his imagination the same hold upon us. For he is
hanging between matter and mind; he is under the dominion at the same
time both of sense and of abstractions; his impressions are taken
almost at random from the outside of nature; he sees the light, but
not the objects which are revealed by the light; and he brings into
juxtaposition things which to us appear wide as the poles asunder,
because he finds nothing between them. He passes abruptly from
persons to ideas and numbers, and from ideas and numbers to
persons,—from the heavens to man, from astronomy to physiology; he
confuses, or rather does not distinguish, subject and object, first
and final causes, and is dreaming of geometrical figures lost in a
flux of sense. He contrasts the perfect movements of the heavenly
bodies with the imperfect representation of them (Rep.), and he does
not always require strict accuracy even in applications of number and
figure (Rep.). His mind lingers around the forms of mythology, which
he uses as symbols or translates into figures of speech. He has no
implements of observation, such as the telescope or microscope; the
great science of chemistry is a blank to him. It is only by an effort
that the modern thinker can breathe the atmosphere of the ancient
philosopher, or understand how, under such unequal conditions, he
seems in many instances, by a sort of inspiration, to have
anticipated the truth.The
influence with the Timaeus has exercised upon posterity is due partly
to a misunderstanding. In the supposed depths of this dialogue the
Neo-Platonists found hidden meanings and connections with the Jewish
and Christian Scriptures, and out of them they elicited doctrines
quite at variance with the spirit of Plato. Believing that he was
inspired by the Holy Ghost, or had received his wisdom from Moses,
they seemed to find in his writings the Christian Trinity, the Word,
the Church, the creation of the world in a Jewish sense, as they
really found the personality of God or of mind, and the immortality
of the soul. All religions and philosophies met and mingled in the
schools of Alexandria, and the Neo-Platonists had a method of
interpretation which could elicit any meaning out of any words. They
were really incapable of distinguishing between the opinions of one
philosopher and another— between Aristotle and Plato, or between
the serious thoughts of Plato and his passing fancies. They were
absorbed in his theology and were under the dominion of his name,
while that which was truly great and truly characteristic in him, his
effort to realize and connect abstractions, was not understood by
them at all. Yet the genius of Plato and Greek philosophy reacted
upon the East, and a Greek element of thought and language overlaid
and partly reduced to order the chaos of Orientalism. And kindred
spirits, like St. Augustine, even though they were acquainted with
his writings only through the medium of a Latin translation, were
profoundly affected by them, seeming to find 'God and his word
everywhere insinuated' in them (August. Confess.)There
is no danger of the modern commentators on the Timaeus falling into
the absurdities of the Neo-Platonists. In the present day we are well
aware that an ancient philosopher is to be interpreted from himself
and by the contemporary history of thought. We know that mysticism is
not criticism. The fancies of the Neo-Platonists are only interesting
to us because they exhibit a phase of the human mind which prevailed
widely in the first centuries of the Christian era, and is not wholly
extinct in our own day. But they have nothing to do with the
interpretation of Plato, and in spirit they are opposed to him. They
are the feeble expression of an age which has lost the power not only
of creating great works, but of understanding them. They are the
spurious birth of a marriage between philosophy and tradition,
between Hellas and the East—(Greek) (Rep.). Whereas the so-called
mysticism of Plato is purely Greek, arising out of his imperfect
knowledge and high aspirations, and is the growth of an age in which
philosophy is not wholly separated from poetry and mythology.A
greater danger with modern interpreters of Plato is the tendency to
regard the Timaeus as the centre of his system. We do not know how
Plato would have arranged his own dialogues, or whether the thought
of arranging any of them, besides the two 'Trilogies' which he has
expressly connected; was ever present to his mind. But, if he had
arranged them, there are many indications that this is not the place
which he would have assigned to the Timaeus. We observe, first of
all, that the dialogue is put into the mouth of a Pythagorean
philosopher, and not of Socrates. And this is required by dramatic
propriety; for the investigation of nature was expressly renounced by
Socrates in the Phaedo. Nor does Plato himself attribute any
importance to his guesses at science. He is not at all absorbed by
them, as he is by the IDEA of good. He is modest and hesitating, and
confesses that his words partake of the uncertainty of the subject
(Tim.). The dialogue is primarily concerned with the animal creation,
including under this term the heavenly bodies, and with man only as
one among the animals. But we can hardly suppose that Plato would
have preferred the study of nature to man, or that he would have
deemed the formation of the world and the human frame to have the
same interest which he ascribes to the mystery of being and
not-being, or to the great political problems which he discusses in
the Republic and the Laws. There are no speculations on physics in
the other dialogues of Plato, and he himself regards the
consideration of them as a rational pastime only. He is beginning to
feel the need of further divisions of knowledge; and is becoming
aware that besides dialectic, mathematics, and the arts, there is
another field which has been hitherto unexplored by him. But he has
not as yet defined this intermediate territory which lies somewhere
between medicine and mathematics, and he would have felt that there
was as great an impiety in ranking theories of physics first in the
order of knowledge, as in placing the body before the soul.It
is true, however, that the Timaeus is by no means confined to
speculations on physics. The deeper foundations of the Platonic
philosophy, such as the nature of God, the distinction of the
sensible and intellectual, the great original conceptions of time and
space, also appear in it. They are found principally in the first
half of the dialogue. The construction of the heavens is for the most
part ideal; the cyclic year serves as the connection between the
world of absolute being and of generation, just as the number of
population in the Republic is the expression or symbol of the
transition from the ideal to the actual state. In some passages we
are uncertain whether we are reading a description of astronomical
facts or contemplating processes of the human mind, or of that divine
mind (Phil.) which in Plato is hardly separable from it. The
characteristics of man are transferred to the world-animal, as for
example when intelligence and knowledge are said to be perfected by
the circle of the Same, and true opinion by the circle of the Other;
and conversely the motions of the world-animal reappear in man; its
amorphous state continues in the child, and in both disorder and
chaos are gradually succeeded by stability and order. It is not
however to passages like these that Plato is referring when he speaks
of the uncertainty of his subject, but rather to the composition of
bodies, to the relations of colours, the nature of diseases, and the
like, about which he truly feels the lamentable ignorance prevailing
in his own age.We
are led by Plato himself to regard the Timaeus, not as the centre or
inmost shrine of the edifice, but as a detached building in a
different style, framed, not after the Socratic, but after some
Pythagorean model. As in the Cratylus and Parmenides, we are
uncertain whether Plato is expressing his own opinions, or
appropriating and perhaps improving the philosophical speculations of
others. In all three dialogues he is exerting his dramatic and
imitative power; in the Cratylus mingling a satirical and humorous
purpose with true principles of language; in the Parmenides
overthrowing Megarianism by a sort of ultra-Megarianism, which
discovers contradictions in the one as great as those which have been
previously shown to exist in the ideas. There is a similar
uncertainty about the Timaeus; in the first part he scales the
heights of transcendentalism, in the latter part he treats in a bald
and superficial manner of the functions and diseases of the human
frame. He uses the thoughts and almost the words of Parmenides when
he discourses of being and of essence, adopting from old religion
into philosophy the conception of God, and from the Megarians the
IDEA of good. He agrees with Empedocles and the Atomists in
attributing the greater differences of kinds to the figures of the
elements and their movements into and out of one another. With
Heracleitus, he acknowledges the perpetual flux; like Anaxagoras, he
asserts the predominance of mind, although admitting an element of
necessity which reason is incapable of subduing; like the
Pythagoreans he supposes the mystery of the world to be contained in
number. Many, if not all the elements of the Pre-Socratic philosophy
are included in the Timaeus. It is a composite or eclectic work of
imagination, in which Plato, without naming them, gathers up into a
kind of system the various elements of philosophy which preceded him.If
we allow for the difference of subject, and for some growth in
Plato's own mind, the discrepancy between the Timaeus and the other
dialogues will not appear to be great. It is probable that the
relation of the ideas to God or of God to the world was differently
conceived by him at different times of his life. In all his later
dialogues we observe a tendency in him to personify mind or God, and
he therefore naturally inclines to view creation as the work of
design. The creator is like a human artist who frames in his mind a
plan which he executes by the help of his servants. Thus the language
of philosophy which speaks of first and second causes is crossed by
another sort of phraseology: 'God made the world because he was good,
and the demons ministered to him.' The Timaeus is cast in a more
theological and less philosophical mould than the other dialogues,
but the same general spirit is apparent; there is the same dualism or
opposition between the ideal and actual—the soul is prior to the
body, the intelligible and unseen to the visible and corporeal. There
is the same distinction between knowledge and opinion which occurs in
the Theaetetus and Republic, the same enmity to the poets, the same
combination of music and gymnastics. The doctrine of transmigration
is still held by him, as in the Phaedrus and Republic; and the soul
has a view of the heavens in a prior state of being. The ideas also
remain, but they have become types in nature, forms of men, animals,
birds, fishes. And the attribution of evil to physical causes accords
with the doctrine which he maintains in the Laws respecting the
involuntariness of vice.The
style and plan of the Timaeus differ greatly from that of any other
of the Platonic dialogues. The language is weighty, abrupt, and in
some passages sublime. But Plato has not the same mastery over his
instrument which he exhibits in the Phaedrus or Symposium. Nothing
can exceed the beauty or art of the introduction, in which he is
using words after his accustomed manner. But in the rest of the work
the power of language seems to fail him, and the dramatic form is
wholly given up. He could write in one style, but not in another, and
the Greek language had not as yet been fashioned by any poet or
philosopher to describe physical phenomena. The early physiologists
had generally written in verse; the prose writers, like Democritus
and Anaxagoras, as far as we can judge from their fragments, never
attained to a periodic style. And hence we find the same sort of
clumsiness in the Timaeus of Plato which characterizes the
philosophical poem of Lucretius. There is a want of flow and often a
defect of rhythm; the meaning is sometimes obscure, and there is a
greater use of apposition and more of repetition than occurs in
Plato's earlier writings. The sentences are less closely connected
and also more involved; the antecedents of demonstrative and relative
pronouns are in some cases remote and perplexing. The greater
frequency of participles and of absolute constructions gives the
effect of heaviness. The descriptive portion of the Timaeus retains
traces of the first Greek prose composition; for the great master of
language was speaking on a theme with which he was imperfectly
acquainted, and had no words in which to express his meaning. The
rugged grandeur of the opening discourse of Timaeus may be compared
with the more harmonious beauty of a similar passage in the Phaedrus.To
the same cause we may attribute the want of plan. Plato had not the
command of his materials which would have enabled him to produce a
perfect work of art. Hence there are several new beginnings and
resumptions and formal or artificial connections; we miss the
'callida junctura' of the earlier dialogues. His speculations about
the Eternal, his theories of creation, his mathematical
anticipations, are supplemented by desultory remarks on the one
immortal and the two mortal souls of man, on the functions of the
bodily organs in health and disease, on sight, hearing, smell, taste,
and touch. He soars into the heavens, and then, as if his wings were
suddenly clipped, he walks ungracefully and with difficulty upon the
earth. The greatest things in the world, and the least things in man,
are brought within the compass of a short treatise. But the
intermediate links are missing, and we cannot be surprised that there
should be a want of unity in a work which embraces astronomy,
theology, physiology, and natural philosophy in a few pages.It
is not easy to determine how Plato's cosmos may be presented to the
reader in a clearer and shorter form; or how we may supply a thread
of connexion to his ideas without giving greater consistency to them
than they possessed in his mind, or adding on consequences which
would never have occurred to him. For he has glimpses of the truth,
but no comprehensive or perfect vision. There are isolated
expressions about the nature of God which have a wonderful depth and
power; but we are not justified in assuming that these had any
greater significance to the mind of Plato than language of a neutral
and impersonal character... With a view to the illustration of the
Timaeus I propose to divide this Introduction into sections, of which
the first will contain an outline of the dialogue: (2) I shall
consider the aspects of nature which presented themselves to Plato
and his age, and the elements of philosophy which entered into the
conception of them: (3) the theology and physics of the Timaeus,
including the soul of the world, the conception of time and space,
and the composition of the elements: (4) in the fourth section I
shall consider the Platonic astronomy, and the position of the earth.
There will remain, (5) the psychology, (6) the physiology of Plato,
and (7) his analysis of the senses to be briefly commented upon: (8)
lastly, we may examine in what points Plato approaches or anticipates
the discoveries of modern science.