On Human Nature
On Human NatureTRANSLATOR'S PREFACE.HUMAN NATURE.GOVERNMENT.FREE-WILL AND FATALISM.CHARACTER.MORAL INSTINCT.ETHICAL REFLECTIONS.Copyright
On Human Nature
Arthur Schopenhauer
TRANSLATOR'S PREFACE.
The following essays are drawn from the chapters
entitledZur EthikandZur Rechtslehre und Politikwhich are
to be found both in Schopenhauer'sParergaand in his posthumous writings.
As in my previous volumes, so also in this, I have omitted a few
passages which appeared to me to be either antiquated or no longer
of any general interest. For convenience' sake I have divided the
original chapters into sections, which I have had to name; and I
have also had to invent a title which should express their real
scope. The reader will find that it is not so muchEthicsandPoliticsthat are here treated, as
human nature itself in various aspects.T.B.S.
HUMAN NATURE.
Truths of the physical order may possess much external
significance, but internal significance they have none. The latter
is the privilege of intellectual and moral truths, which are
concerned with the objectivation of the will in its highest stages,
whereas physical truths are concerned with it in its
lowest.For example, if we could establish the truth of what up till
now is only a conjecture, namely, that it is the action of the sun
which produces thermoelectricity at the equator; that this produces
terrestrial magnetism; and that this magnetism, again, is the cause
of theaurora borealis, these
would be truths externally of great, but internally of little,
significance. On the other hand, examples of internal significance
are furnished by all great and true philosophical systems; by the
catastrophe of every good tragedy; nay, even by the observation of
human conduct in the extreme manifestations of its morality and
immorality, of its good and its evil character. For all these are
expressions of that reality which takes outward shape as the world,
and which, in the highest stages of its objectivation, proclaims
its innermost nature.To say that the world has only a physical and not a moral
significance is the greatest and most pernicious of all errors, the
fundamental blunder, the real perversity of mind and temper; and,
at bottom, it is doubtless the tendency which faith personifies as
Anti-Christ. Nevertheless, in spite of all religions—and they are
systems which one and all maintain the opposite, and seek to
establish it in their mythical way—this fundamental error never
becomes quite extinct, but raises its head from time to time
afresh, until universal indignation compels it to hide itself once
more.Yet, however certain we may feel of the moral significance of
life and the world, to explain and illustrate it, and to resolve
the contradiction between this significance and the world as it is,
form a task of great difficulty; so great, indeed, as to make it
possible that it has remained for me to exhibit the true and only
genuine and sound basis of morality everywhere and at all times
effective, together with the results to which it leads. The actual
facts of morality are too much on my side for me to fear that my
theory can ever be replaced or upset by any other.However, so long as even my ethical system continues to be
ignored by the professorial world, it is Kant's moral principle
that prevails in the universities. Among its various forms the one
which is most in favour at present is "the dignity of man." I have
already exposed the absurdity of this doctrine in my treatise on
theFoundation of Morality.[1]
Therefore I will only say here that if the question were asked on
what the alleged dignity of man rests, it would not be long before
the answer was made that it rests upon his morality. In other
words, his morality rests upon his dignity, and his dignity rests
upon his morality.[Footnote 1: § 8.]But apart from this circular argument it seems to me that the
idea of dignity can be applied only in an ironical sense to a being
whose will is so sinful, whose intellect is so limited, whose body
is so weak and perishable as man's. How shall a man be proud, when
his conception is a crime, his birth a penalty, his life a labour,
and death a necessity!—Quid superbit homo? cujus conceptio culpa, Nasci poena,
labor vita, necesse mori!Therefore, in opposition to the above-mentioned form of the
Kantian principle, I should be inclined to lay down the following
rule: When you come into contact with a man, no matter whom, do not
attempt an objective appreciation of him according to his worth and
dignity. Do not consider his bad will, or his narrow understanding
and perverse ideas; as the former may easily lead you to hate and
the latter to despise him; but fix your attention only upon his
sufferings, his needs, his anxieties, his pains. Then you will
always feel your kinship with him; you will sympathise with him;
and instead of hatred or contempt you will experience the
commiseration that alone is the peace to which the Gospel calls us.
The way to keep down hatred and contempt is certainly not to look
for a man's alleged "dignity," but, on the contrary, to regard him
as an object of pity.The Buddhists, as the result of the more profound views which
they entertain on ethical and metaphysical subjects, start from the
cardinal vices and not the cardinal virtues; since the virtues make
their appearance only as the contraries or negations of the vices.
According to Schmidt'sHistory of the Eastern
Mongoliansthe cardinal vices in the Buddhist
scheme are four: Lust, Indolence, Anger, and Avarice. But probably
instead of Indolence, we should read Pride; for so it stands in
theLettres édifiantes et curieuses,[1] where Envy, or Hatred, is added as a fifth. I am
confirmed in correcting the statement of the excellent Schmidt by
the fact that my rendering agrees with the doctrine of the Sufis,
who are certainly under the influence of the Brahmins and
Buddhists. The Sufis also maintain that there are four cardinal
vices, and they arrange them in very striking pairs, so that Lust
appears in connection with Avarice, and Anger with Pride. The four
cardinal virtues opposed to them would be Chastity and Generosity,
together with Gentleness and Humility.[Footnote 1: Edit, of 1819, vol. vi., p. 372.]When we compare these profound ideas of morality, as they are
entertained by oriental nations, with the celebrated cardinal
virtues of Plato, which have been recapitulated again and
again—Justice, Valour, Temperance, and Wisdom—it is plain that the
latter are not based on any clear, leading idea, but are chosen on
grounds that are superficial and, in part, obviously false. Virtues
must be qualities of the will, but Wisdom is chiefly an attribute
of the Intellect. [Greek: Sophrosynae], which Cicero
translatesTemperantia, is a
very indefinite and ambiguous word, and it admits, therefore, of a
variety of applications: it may mean discretion, or abstinence, or
keeping a level head. Courage is not a virtue at all; although
sometimes it is a servant or instrument of virtue; but it is just
as ready to become the servant of the greatest villainy. It is
really a quality of temperament. Even Geulinx (in the preface to
thisEthics) condemned the
Platonic virtues and put the following in their place: Diligence,
Obedience, Justice and Humility; which are obviously bad. The
Chinese distinguish five cardinal virtues: Sympathy, Justice,
Propriety, Wisdom, and Sincerity. The virtues of Christianity are
theological, not cardinal: Faith, Love, and Hope.Fundamental disposition towards others, assuming the
character either of Envy or of Sympathy, is the point at which the
moral virtues and vices of mankind first diverge. These two
diametrically opposite qualities exist in every man; for they
spring from the inevitable comparison which he draws between his
own lot and that of others. According as the result of this
comparison affects his individual character does the one or the
other of these qualities become the source and principle of all his
action. Envy builds the wall betweenTheeandMethicker and stronger; Sympathy makes
it slight and transparent; nay, sometimes it pulls down the wall
altogether; and then the distinction between self and not-self
vanishes.Valour, which has been mentioned as a virtue, or rather the
Courage on which it is based (for valour is only courage in war),
deserves a closer examination. The ancients reckoned Courage among
the virtues, and cowardice among the vices; but there is no
corresponding idea in the Christian scheme, which makes for charity
and patience, and in its teaching forbids all enmity or even
resistance. The result is that with the moderns Courage is no
longer a virtue. Nevertheless it must be admitted that cowardice
does not seem to be very compatible with any nobility of
character—if only for the reason that it betrays an overgreat
apprehension about one's own person.Courage, however, may also be explained as a readiness to
meet ills that threaten at the moment, in order to avoid greater
ills that lie in the future; whereas cowardice does the contrary.
But this readiness is of the same quality aspatience, for patience consists in the
clear consciousness that greater evils than those which are
present, and that any violent attempt to flee from or guard against
the ills we have may bring the others upon us. Courage, then, would
be a kind of patience; and since it is patience that enables us to
practise forbearance and self control, Courage is, through the
medium of patience, at least akin to virtue.But perhaps Courage admits of being considered from a higher
point of view. The fear of death may in every case be traced to a
deficiency in that natural philosophy—natural, and therefore
resting on mere feeling—which gives a man the assurance that he
exists in everything outside him just as much as in his own person;
so that the death of his person can do him little harm. But it is
just this very assurance that would give a man heroic Courage; and
therefore, as the reader will recollect from myEthics, Courage comes from the same
source as the virtues of Justice and Humanity. This is, I admit, to
take a very high view of the matter; but apart from it I cannot
well explain why cowardice seems contemptible, and personal courage
a noble and sublime thing; for no lower point of view enables me to
see why a finite individual who is everything to himself—nay, who
is himself even the very fundamental condition of the existence of
the rest of the world—should not put his own preservation above
every other aim. It is, then, an insufficient explanation of
Courage to make it rest only on utility, to give it an empirical
and not a transcendental character. It may have been for some such
reason that Calderon once uttered a sceptical but remarkable
opinion in regard to Courage, nay, actually denied its reality; and
put his denial into the mouth of a wise old minister, addressing
his young sovereign. "Although," he observed, "natural fear is
operative in all alike, a man may be brave in not letting it be
seen; and it is this that constitutes Courage":Que aunque el natural
temor En todos obra igualmente, No mostrarle es ser
valiente Y esto es lo que hace el valor.[1][Footnote 1:La Hija del Aire, ii., 2.]In regard to the difference which I have mentioned between
the ancients and the moderns in their estimate of Courage as a
virtue, it must be remembered that by Virtue,virtus, [Greek: aretae], the ancients
understood every excellence or quality that was praiseworthy in
itself, it might be moral or intellectual, or possibly only
physical. But when Christianity demonstrated that the fundamental
tendency of life was moral, it was moral superiority alone than
henceforth attached to the notion of Virtue. Meanwhile the earlier
usage still survived in the elder Latinists, and also in Italian
writers, as is proved by the well-known meaning of the wordvirtuoso. The special attention of
students should be drawn to this wider range of the idea of Virtue
amongst the ancients, as otherwise it might easily be a source of
secret perplexity. I may recommend two passages preserved for us by
Stobaeus, which will serve this purpose. One of them is apparently
from the Pythagorean philosopher Metopos, in which the fitness of
every bodily member is declared to be a virtue. The other
pronounces that the virtue of a shoemaker is to make good shoes.
This may also serve to explain why it is that in the ancient scheme
of ethics virtues and vices are mentioned which find no place in
ours.As the place of Courage amongst the virtues is a matter of
doubt, so is that of Avarice amongst the vices. It must not,
however, be confounded with greed, which is the most immediate
meaning of the Latin wordavaritia. Let us then draw up and examine the argumentspro et contrain regard to Avarice, and
leave the final judgment to be formed by every man for
himself.On the one hand it is argued that it is not Avarice which is
a vice, but extravagance, its opposite. Extravagance springs from a
brutish limitation to the present moment, in comparison with which
the future, existing as it does only in thought, is as nothing. It
rests upon the illusion that sensual pleasures possess a positive
or real value. Accordingly, future need and misery is the price at
which the spendthrift purchases pleasures that are empty, fleeting,
and often no more than imaginary; or else feeds his vain, stupid
self-conceit on the bows and scrapes of parasites who laugh at him
in secret, or on the gaze of the mob and those who envy his
magnificence. We should, therefore, shun the spendthrift as though
he had the plague, and on discovering his vice break with him
betimes, in order that later on, when the consequences of his
extravagance ensue, we may neither have to help to bear them, nor,
on the other hand, have to play the part of the friends of Timon of
Athens.At the same time it is not to be expected that he who
foolishly squanders his own fortune will leave another man's
intact, if it should chance to be committed to his keeping;
nay,sui profususandalieni appetensare by Sallust very
rightly conjoined. Hence it is that extravagance leads not only to
impoverishment but also to crime; and crime amongst the moneyed
classes is almost always the result of extravagance. It is
accordingly with justice that theKorandeclares all spendthrifts to be
"brothers of Satan."But it is superfluity that Avarice brings in its train, and
when was superfluity ever unwelcome? That must be a good vice which
has good consequences. Avarice proceeds upon the principle that all
pleasure is only negative in its operation and that the happiness
which consists of a series of pleasures is a chimaera; that, on the
contrary, it is pains which are positive and extremely real.
Accordingly, the avaricious man foregoes the former in order that
he may be the better preserved from the latter, and thus it is
thatbear and forbear—sustine et abstine—is his maxim. And
because he knows, further, how inexhaustible are the possibilities
of misfortune, and how innumerable the paths of danger, he
increases the means of avoiding them, in order, if possible, to
surround himself with a triple wall of protection. Who, then, can
say where precaution against disaster begins to be exaggerated? He
alone who knows where the malignity of fate reaches its limit. And
even if precaution were exaggerated it is an error which at the
most would hurt the man who took it, and not others. If he will
never need the treasures which he lays up for himself, they will
one day benefit others whom nature has made less careful. That
until then he withdraws the money from circulation is no
misfortune; for money is not an article of consumption: it only
represents the good things which a man may actually possess, and is
not one itself. Coins are only counters; their value is what they
represent; and what they represent cannot be withdrawn from
circulation. Moreover, by holding back the money, the value of the
remainder which is in circulation is enhanced by precisely the same
amount. Even though it be the case, as is said, that many a miser
comes in the end to love money itself for its own sake, it is
equally certain that many a spendthrift, on the other hand, loves
spending and squandering for no better reason. Friendship with a
miser is not only without danger, but it is profitable, because of
the great advantages it can bring. For it is doubtless those who
are nearest and dearest to the miser who on his death will reap the
fruits of the self-control which he exercised; but even in his
lifetime, too, something may be expected of him in cases of great
need. At any rate one can always hope for more from him than from
the spendthrift, who has lost his all and is himself helpless and
in debt.Mas da el duro que el desnudo, says a Spanish proverb; the man who has a hard heart will
give more than the man who has an empty purse. The upshot of all
this is that Avarice is not a vice.On the other side, it may be said that Avarice is the
quintessence of all vices. When physical pleasures seduce a man
from the right path, it is his sensual nature—the animal part of
him—which is at fault. He is carried away by its attractions, and,
overcome by the impression of the moment, he acts without thinking
of the consequences. When, on the other hand, he is brought by age
or bodily weakness to the condition in which the vices that he
could never abandon end by abandoning him, and his capacity for
physical pleasure dies—if he turns to Avarice, the intellectual
desire survives the sensual. Money, which represents all the good
things of this world, and is these good things in the abstract, now
becomes the dry trunk overgrown with all the dead lusts of the
flesh, which are egoism in the abstract. They come to life again in
the love of the Mammon. The transient pleasure of the senses has
become a deliberate and calculated lust of money, which, like that
to which it is directed, is symbolical in its nature, and, like it,
indestructible.This obstinate love of the pleasures of the world—a love
which, as it were, outlives itself; this utterly incorrigible sin,
this refined and sublimated desire of the flesh, is the abstract
form in which all lusts are concentrated, and to which it stands
like a general idea to individual particulars. Accordingly, Avarice
is the vice of age, just as extravagance is the vice of
youth.Thisdisputatio in utramque
partem—this debate for and against—is certainly
calculated to drive us into accepting thejuste
milieumorality of Aristotle; a conclusion that
is also supported by the following consideration.