Social and Political Science - Rudolf Steiner - E-Book

Social and Political Science E-Book

Rudolf Steiner

0,0
7,00 €

oder
-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

Psychological cognition; The social question; The social question and theosophy; Memoranda of 1917; The metamorphosis of intelligence; Culture, law and economy; Central Europe between East and West.

Das E-Book können Sie in Legimi-Apps oder einer beliebigen App lesen, die das folgende Format unterstützen:

EPUB
Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



SOCIAL AND POLITICAL SCIENCE

Also available:

(Practical Applications)

Agriculture

Architecture

Art

Education

Medicine

Religion

Science

(Esoteric)

Alchemy

Atlantis

Christian Rozenkreutz

The Druids

The Goddess

The Holy Grail

RUDOLF STEINER

SOCIAL AND POLITICAL SCIENCE

An Introductory Reader

Compiled with an introduction, commentary and notes by Stephen E. Usher

Sophia Books

All translations revised by Christian von Arnim

Sophia Books An imprint of Rudolf Steiner Press Hillside House, The Square Forest Row, RH18 5ES

www.rudolfsteinerpress.com

Published by Rudolf Steiner Press 2012

For earlier English publications of individual selections please see Sources

The material by Rudolf Steiner was originally published in German in various volumes of the ‘GA’ (Rudolf Steiner Gesamtausgabe or Collected Works) by Rudolf Steiner Verlag, Dornach. This authorized volume is published by permission of the Rudolf Steiner Nachlassverwaltung, Dornach (for further information see Note Regarding Rudolf Steiner’s Lectures)

This selection and translation © Rudolf Steiner Press 2003

All rights reserved. No part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system, or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publishers

A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library

ISBN 978 1 85584 336 3

Cover design by Andrew Morgan Typeset by DP Photosetting, Aylesbury, Bucks.

Contents

Introduction: Seminal Ideas and Historic Moments by Stephen E. Usher

1. Psychological Cognition

2. The Social Question

3. The Social Question and Theosophy

4. Memoranda of 1917

5. The Metamorphosis of Intelligence

6. Culture, Law and Economy

7. Central Europe between East and West

Notes

Sources

Further Reading

Note Regarding Rudolf Steiner’s Lectures

Introduction: Seminal Ideas and Historic Moments

by Stephen Usher

Rudolf Steiner (1861-1925) is best remembered today for establishing Waldorf education, a movement which has produced hundreds of schools around the world for children from kindergarten to school-leaving age. His reputation was different immediately after the First World War when he was recognized throughout Europe and the United States as a social thinker who had proposed an alternative to both communism and capitalism as a path for the reconstruction of post-war Central Europe. One British commentator, writing in the London Quarterly Review, stated that Steiner’s book Towards Social Renewal was ‘perhaps the most widely read of all books on politics appearing since the war’.1 That book was also reviewed in significant places in the US such as the New York Times Review of Books, Journal of Political Economy, and The American Economic Review.2

Of course the twentieth century witnessed the struggle of capitalism versus communism to become the model for human social organization. When the Berlin Wall fell in 1989, capitalism was declared the victor, a notion trumpeted particularly by Francis Fukuyama in his End of History and the Last Man. The struggle between those two world views left little room for awareness of a third alternative during the course of the last century, particularly as Steiner’s ideas lacked a ‘laboratory’ to unfold themselves.

But the victory of capitalism is hollow for it has failed to deliver even a tolerable material existence to much of the earth’s population, to say nothing of a more spiritual sense of fulfilment. For this reason it seems appropriate to bring before the public today this selection of Steiner’s social ideas, which are like seeds from some Vavilovian centre that have lain dormant for many years but still retain their power of germination. They offer something vital to humanity’s social thinking, which has grown sterile over the long course of the twentieth century.

The selection is arranged chronologically. It begins with the 24-year-old Steiner’s discussion of the difference between the methods of the life sciences and the social sciences from ‘Psychological cognition’, a chapter of his A Theory of Knowledge Based on Goethe’s World Conception. His 1898 article from Das Magazin für Literatur, entitled ‘The social question’, is the second selection. Here Steiner develops what he calls the fundamental sociological law: ‘In the early stages of cultural evolution, mankind tends towards the formation of social units; initially the interests of individuals are sacrificed to the interests of those groupings; the further progress of development leads to the emancipation of the individual from the interests of the groupings and to the unrestricted development of needs and capacities of the individual.’ He describes the goal and social ideal of this evolution as ‘anarchistic individualism’.

In 1905 Steiner wrote an essay titled ‘The science of the spiritual and the social question’3 in which he develops what is for him a fundamental social law: ‘The well-being of a total community of human beings working together becomes greater the less the individual demands the products of his achievements for himself, that is, the more of these products he passes on to his fellow workers and the more his own needs are not satisfied out of his own achievements, but out of the achievements of others.’ On 26 October 1905, he delivered a lecture titled ‘The social question and theosophy’ where he develops the same set of concepts using different examples, and it is this lecture that is our third selection.

It is worth observing that on 26 July 1922, when he delivered the cycle of lectures published under the title World Economy,4 Steiner commented about this fundamental social law that ‘it would only have had real significance if it had been taken up by men of affairs and if they had acted accordingly. But it was left altogether unnoticed; consequently I did not complete it or publish any more of it.’ He proceeded, in these lectures of 1922, to link the concept of the division of labour to his concept of the fundamental social law, showing that when economic production was dominated by large-scale division of labour the law was achieved, in a certain sense, because then the worker in what he is actually doing is literally providing for the needs of others far more than is the case in more primitive economic conditions. (A worker on an assembly line, perhaps, stamps a single piece of metal thousands of times per day and these go into thousands of cars that meet the needs of thousands of people all around the world. By contrast, in a primitive community a person spends part of his time farming and part of his time spinning yarn, which meets his own needs and that of his immediate family and perhaps, through barter, the needs of a few more people in his immediate circle.) From this fact flows the great vitality of the modern economic process, but this vitality is contradicted by the selfish motivation that brings people to work. A particularly clear explanation of how Steiner’s threefold social organization would make possible a different type of motivation to work is found in the collection of Steiner’s newspaper articles of the early 1920s published under the title Renewal of the Social Organism.5 The argument is ably summarized in Joseph Weizenbaum’s foreword to this volume.

Steiner’s ‘law of true price’, which he first formulated in a footnote to Towards Social Renewal6 (1919) and elaborated in the lecture of 29 July 1922 in World Economy, is also closely related to his fundamental social law. Indeed, the law of true price is a way of bringing about the fundamental social law in an economy based on market prices in such a way that both the actual production and the motivation to work are consistent with the law and that maximum anarchical individualism is possible. Steiner states the law of true price as follows: ‘A true price is forthcoming when a man receives, as counter-value for the product he has made, sufficient to enable him to satisfy the whole of his needs, including of course the needs of his dependants, until he will again have completed a like product.’7

From these brief comments one gets a glimpse of how Steiner first developed his observations about the fundamental social law in seed form and how after an interval of 14 years he returned to it again and showed how the idea expanded and developed like a plant that metamorphoses from seed to leaf to blossom. During the period between 1905 and the outbreak of the First World War in 1914, Steiner said little about social issues, at least in a direct way. Then in 1915 he returned to social concerns with his essay ‘Thoughts during the time of war, to the Germans and those who do not believe they have to hate them.’8

It was in June and July of 1917 that he introduced his seminal idea of the threefold social order. He developed the idea in response to the question of Otto Lerchenfeld (1868-1938), who worked in the Berlin government during these difficult war years. Lerchenfeld came to Steiner with the question: Is there any way out of the catastrophic situation that has engulfed Europe? (The war had raged for three long years and, before it was over, more than 30 million people had died.) Steiner responded by giving Lerchenfeld a three-week private seminar on the threefold social order. Lerchenfeld gave a brief description of his experience in his memoirs, as follows:

More than three weeks of day-long, hour-long work followed this first conference. They were weeks of the loftiest experience, the highest tension, the most intense learning; learning what logic of life is in truth; learning of becoming and fading away; learning how logic must encompass life in an artistic way; learning how it must not weaken upon contact with real life and become illogical. Politics is art and not science alone. When it is only mere science it makes the social organism ill because the organism is then handled as a dead thing.

And then one beautiful day the complete structure was there, put together stone upon stone in the utmost detail. There was nothing of the abstract, no theory, no programme, nothing merely thought out. These have nothing to do with the onward movement of life. In the building of this structure, on the other hand, every one of the weighty relations of life was asked, as it were: ‘What do you need, and you and you, in order to prosper as freely, joyfully, and soundly as possible and to become what you might become and ought to become if you are to be able to fulfil your mission in the totality of the social order?’ And the answers of all, as if bound together in a garland, did not provide what was intended to become a definitive solution of the social question, and could naturally not be this by reason of the very nature of a living organism. Nevertheless, there did result out of this idea the way, the only straightforward way upon which the social conditions, the social difficulties with their eternally varying problems, might be guided again and again towards a solution appropriate to the period, towards their curing.9

Following this seminar, Steiner developed a plan together with Lerchenfeld and Ludwig Polzer-Hoditz (1869-1945) to bring about an armistice on the condition that Central Europe be permitted to reconstruct itself on the basis of the threefold social order. As such it was an alternative to the idea of a ‘peace without victory’10 then being circulated by the American president Woodrow Wilson.

To bring about this plan Steiner drafted his two memoranda of 1917 and these two memoranda constitute the next item presented in this collection. They are not easy reading for contemporaries because they are directed to the senior statesmen of the Austro-Hungarian Empire and of the Germany of that day. As such they assume a reader intimately familiar with the history of those regions, including all the important events of the war and its outbreak. Naturally they also assume a reader familiar with the state structures of these countries at that time.

In addition to introducing the concept of the threefold social order, the memoranda offered the statesmen a perspective on the outbreak of the war and where lay responsibility for that catastrophe; on the manner in which the British were managing war propaganda to their extreme advantage; and on esoteric considerations about the geo-political aspirations of the Anglo-American world and how these worked into the war. The memoranda really should be read together with two other documents that were known to Steiner and that support the position he took in the memoranda.11 The first is the 1914 memoir on the outbreak of the war12 written by Helmuth von Moltke, chief-of-staff of the German army at the outbreak of the war. This provides a unique insight into the state of the German leadership at that time and supports Steiner’s thesis that Germany was not solely responsible for the war, a view which is contrary to the weight of historical opinion and the clause of the Treaty of Versailles attributing sole guilt to the Germans.13

In particular, von Moltke’s memoir presents a symptomatological picture of the whole illness of the German leadership.14 Von Moltke describes how Kaiser Wilhelm briefly halted western mobilization of the German army due to a mistaken hope that the British were about to agree to remain neutral and guarantee that the French would not attack. Given the precision timing and coordination required in those times to mobilize an army of one million soldiers, interfering with the mobilization was extremely risky as it could have brought about complete chaos with catastrophic consequences for Germany. That the mobilization was halted indicates how little the political leadership understood the military’s Schlieffen Plan that was the only military option available.15 That plan called for a rapid dual front assault to the west and the east and was created out of an understanding of the complex treaties that governed international relations at the time. The treaty between the Russians and the French, in particular, required both to go to the defence of the other if war broke out. While the halt demonstrated that the political leadership was out of touch with reality when it entertained the idea that the British would give such a guarantee, it also shows that they were not hell bent on a two-front war and thus supports Steiner’s contention that the British bore part of the responsibility for the western war as they could have prevented it by making the guarantee.

When confronted with the Kaiser’s decision, von Moltke was greatly disturbed because he understood the implications of halting the mobilization and he entertained no delusions that such a guarantee would be forthcoming from England. In his memoir von Moltke explained how he argued that the mobilization should not be halted but rather carried forward so that the western part of the mobilization stop at the western German frontier. Then, if the guarantee were made, troops could be shifted to the east to counter the Russian mobilization that already was underway. Several hours after the Kaiser had called for the halt of the mobilization he received a telegram from his cousin, the King of England, advising that Britain would make no such guarantee. At this point the Kaiser summoned von Moltke and told him that he could do as he pleased.

This bizarre incident should be recognized for its value as a historical symptom. It is a historic experiment that reveals the intentions and confusion of the Kaiser and German government at the outbreak of the war. To use modern language, it is an asset-backed demonstration that they would not have invaded Belgium or France if they had received the British guarantee. Historians have largely ignored this remarkable piece of evidence.

Without the evidence of this symptom one might dismiss the conversation between the German ambassador to Britain, Lichnowsky, and the British Foreign Minister (Grey) as posturing on the part of the Germans, suggesting as Grey did that the ambassador was not speaking on behalf of his government. This conversation, which is itself another important symptom, is preserved in an official British telegram from Grey to the British ambassador to Berlin, Goschen:

I told the German ambassador today that the reply of the German government with regard to the neutrality of Belgium affected feeling in this country. If Germany could see her way to give the same assurances as that which had been given by France it would materially contribute to relieve anxiety and tension here. On the other hand, if there were a violation of the neutrality of Belgium by one combatant while the other respected it, it would be extremely difficult to restrain public feeling in this country. I said that we had been discussing this question at a Cabinet meeting, and, as I was authorized to tell him this, I gave him an aide-mémoire of it.

He asked me whether, if Germany gave a promise not to violate Belgian neutrality, we would engage to remain neutral.

I replied that I could not say that; our hands were still free, and we were considering what our attitude should be. All I could say was that our attitude would be determined largely by public opinion16 here, and that the neutrality of Belgium would appeal very strongly to public opinion here. I did not think that we could give a promise of neutrality on that condition alone.

The Ambassador pressed me as to whether I could not formulate conditions on which we would remain neutral. He even suggested that the integrity of France and her colonies might be guaranteed.

I said that I felt obliged to refuse definitely any promise to remain neutral on similar terms, and I could only say that we must keep our hands free.17

The second item that deserves to be read together with Steiner’s memoranda is the book The Transcendental Universe: Six lectures on Occult Science, Theosophy and the Catholic Faith by C.G. Harrison.18 This volume was originally published in 1894 in England and it gives a unique look into the esoteric knowledge alive in England at the time and supports some of the statements made by Steiner in the memoranda.

Before leaving the theme of the Harrison book and Steiner’s remarks in the memoranda about the secret societies that worked behind the scenes of the British and American governments, it should also be remarked that Steiner was highly critical of what developed in Germany after 1871.19 In his preface to the von Moltke memoir Steiner argues that Germany had no business aspiring to become a world power based on ‘exercise of power’. Rather it should have developed itself along a line consistent with its pre-1871 history as a cultural power as reflected, for example, in the idealist philosophers, Goethe, Schiller, the great musicians etc.20 That was its rightful path of development. It also should be made clear that Steiner was not in sympathy with German nationalists. Indeed, Hitler attacked Steiner in print in 1921 and, in 1922, the early nationalists attempted to kill Steiner in Munich.21

The thrust of Steiner’s advice in the memoranda to the Central European statesmen is that they should find the courage to proclaim to the world that they intended to move Central Europe forward, beyond the war, with the threefold social order as the organizational principle. According to Steiner the very appearance of this concept, issuing from the governing power of Central Europe, would paralyse the esoteric ambitions of the hidden Anglo-American establishment. Had they found the courage to follow this advice they would have brought about a legitimate and balancing centre between West and East that would have allowed a much healthier evolution of mankind over the twentieth century. Steiner’s objective in giving this advice to the statesmen was to put Germany back on the course of its pre-1871 development. He viewed his threefold social order as arising from the real thread of middle European cultural development and history.

With the help of Ludwig Poltzer-Hoditz, Otto Lerchenfeld and others, the memoranda reached the hands of leading statesmen in Germany and Austro-Hungary. Ludwig Polzer-Hoditz had a brother, Arthur, who was the private secretary to the young emperor, Karl, of Austro-Hungary and through that channel Karl received a copy of the memoranda. But Karl never managed to pay sufficient attention to the ideas until it was too late.22

The memoranda also reached Prince Max von Baden who had several private conversations with Steiner on the topic of the threefold social order.23 This happened prior to the end of the war when von Baden was made Imperial Chancellor by Kaiser Wilhelm and charged with negotiating an armistice. Steiner had hoped that von Baden would put forth the threefold idea as an alternative to Woodrow Wilson’s 14-point programme. But at the last minute von Baden lost courage and on 5 October 1918 he accepted the Wilson programme as the basis of an armistice. Steiner refers to this failure in his 1919 book Towards Social Renewal with these words, ‘[T]he terrible spiritual capitulation came, brought on by a man in whom many in German lands had placed something like a last hope.’24‘25

With von Baden’s failure there was no further hope that the threefold idea would be proposed to the world by Central European governments as the basis for an armistice. Steiner consequently turned his attention to bringing the idea to the grassroots in Central Europe. In his further attempts to promote the idea of the threefold social order Steiner never again referred to the secret esoteric circles of the Anglo-American world in such a direct fashion as he had done in the memoranda, as there was no longer any reason to do so. The only possibility of creating a countervailing power had been destroyed.26 Moreover, Steiner recognized that the leadership of the historic evolution of mankind had passed into the hands of the West and that civilization would only be prevented from ruin if the English-speaking world could find the insight to pour spirit into the economic impulses that it would pursue.27

The last three items in our selection can be viewed as part of this effort to stimulate a grassroots interest in the threefold idea, which also included his widely circulated ‘Appeal to the German People’.28 This was circulated as a newspaper insert by the hundreds of thousands across Central Europe in March of 1919. This effort also included the publication of Steiner’s Towards Social Renewal in April of 1919.

In two of the remaining selections of this volume Steiner describes his own insights into the esoteric make-up of the peoples of the West, the East and the middle. Here he tries to convey his understanding of the idiosyncratic characteristics of different parts of the globe at the time which he felt needed to be understood by the peoples of the world if they were ever to live in harmony with one another. The remaining chapter of this volume, ‘Culture, Law and Economies’, is a newspaper article Steiner wrote at the end of 1919 when he was attempting to gain grassroots support for his threefold idea. It gives what is for my mind a particularly clear, short statement of the central idea.

1. Psychological Cognition

‘Psychological Cognition’ is a chapter from Rudolf Steiner’s first book, A Theory of Knowledge Based on Goethe’s World Conception.29 Steiner wrote this work when he was 24 years of age. An earlier section of the book is an enquiry regarding the difference between the sciences that study inorganic nature and those that study organic nature. Steiner argues that the study of organic nature already requires a kind of consciousness that transcends what is needed to study the dead world. Moreover, modern civilization is based on the type of consciousness that is appropriate for penetrating the laws of the dead world. To grasp the world of living things already requires stepping beyond the consciousness of our time. He develops the concept of the ‘type’ as the way to approach the living world. The following section of the book is titled, ‘The spiritual or cultural sciences’. It is in this section that the chapter presented here is found. This section concerns itself with a form of consciousness that transcends what is needed to grasp the living world. It is what is needed to penetrate into the lawfulness of the world of ensouled beings. This realm includes what we know as psychology, sociology, political science, economics and history.

The first science in which the human spirit deals with itself is psychology. The mind here stands observing itself.

Fichte assigned an existence to the human being only to the extent that the human being ascribes this to himself. In other words, human personality has only those traits, characteristics, capacities which it ascribes to itself through insight into its own being. A human capacity of which the human being knew nothing would not be recognized by him as his own but would be attributed to someone alien to him. When Fichte supposed that he could base the whole knowledge of the universe on this truth, he was in error. It is appropriate to be the highest principle of psychology. It determines the method of psychology. If the human spirit possesses a characteristic only in so far as it attributes this to itself, then the psychological method consists in the immersion of the mind in its own activity. Here, then, self-apprehension is the method.

It is obvious that in this discussion we do not restrict psychology to being the science of the accidental characteristics of any single (this one or that one) human individual. We release the single mind from its accidental limitations, from its accessory traits, and seek to raise ourselves to a consideration of the human individual as such.