The Meaning of Truth
The Meaning of TruthPREFACEIIIIIIIVVVIVIIVIIIIXXXIXIIXIIIXIVXVCopyright
The Meaning of Truth
William James
PREFACE
THE pivotal part of my book named Pragmatism is its account
of the relation called 'truth' which may obtain between an idea
(opinion, belief, statement, or what not) and its object. 'Truth,'
I there say, 'is a property of certain of our ideas. It means their
agreement, as falsity means their disagreement, with reality.
Pragmatists and intellectualists both accept this definition as a
matter of course.'Where our ideas [do] not copy definitely their object, what
does agreement with that object mean? ... Pragmatism asks its usual
question. "Grant an idea or belief to be true," it says, "what
concrete difference will its being true make in any one's actual
life? What experiences [may] be different from those which would
obtain if the belief were false? How will the truth be realized?
What, in short, is the truth's cash-value in experiential terms?"
The moment pragmatism asks this question, it sees the answer: TRUE
IDEAS ARE THOSE THAT WE CAN ASSIMILATE, VALIDATE, CORROBORATE, AND
VERIFY. FALSE IDEAS ARE THOSE THAT WE CANNOT. That is the practical
difference it makes to us to have true ideas; that therefore is the
meaning of truth, for it is all that truth is known
as.'The truth of an idea is not a stagnant property inherent in
it. Truth HAPPENS to an idea. It BECOMES true, is MADE true by
events. Its verity IS in fact an event, a process, the process
namely of its verifying itself, its veriFICATION. Its validity is
the process of its validATION. [Footnote: But 'VERIFIABILITY,' I
add, 'is as good as verification. For one truth-process completed,
there are a million in our lives that function in [the] state of
nascency. They lead us towards direct verification; lead us into
the surroundings of the object they envisage; and then, if
everything, runs on harmoniously, we are so sure that verification
is possible that we omit it, and are usually justified by all that
happens.']'To agree in the widest sense with a reality can only mean to
be guided either straight up to it or into its surroundings, or to
be put into such working touch with it as to handle either it or
something connected with it better than if we disagreed. Better
either intellectually or practically .... Any idea that helps us to
deal, whether practically or intellectually, with either the
reality or its belongings, that doesn't entangle our progress in
frustrations, that FITS, in fact, and adapts our life to the
reality's whole setting, will agree sufficiently to meet the
requirement. It will be true of that reality.'THE TRUE, to put it very briefly, IS ONLY THE EXPEDIENT IN
THE WAY OF OUR THINKING, JUST AS THE RIGHT IS ONLY THE EXPEDIENT IN
THE WAY OF OUR BEHAVING. Expedient in almost any fashion, and
expedient in the long run and on the whole, of course; for what
meets expediently all the experience in sight won't necessarily
meet all farther experiences equally satisfactorily. Experience, as
we know, has ways of BOILING OVER, and making us correct our
present formulas.'This account of truth, following upon the similar ones given
by Messrs. Dewey and Schiller, has occasioned the liveliest
discussion. Few critics have defended it, most of them have scouted
it. It seems evident that the subject is a hard one to understand,
under its apparent simplicity; and evident also, I think, that the
definitive settlement of it will mark a turning-point in the
history of epistemology, and consequently in that of general
philosophy. In order to make my own thought more accessible to
those who hereafter may have to study the question, I have
collected in the volume that follows all the work of my pen that
bears directly on the truth-question. My first statement was in
1884, in the article that begins the present volume. The other
papers follow in the order of their publication. Two or three
appear now for the first time.One of the accusations which I oftenest have had to meet is
that of making the truth of our religious beliefs consist in their
'feeling good' to us, and in nothing else. I regret to have given
some excuse for this charge, by the unguarded language in which, in
the book Pragmatism, I spoke of the truth of the belief of certain
philosophers in the absolute. Explaining why I do not believe in
the absolute myself (p. 78), yet finding that it may secure 'moral
holidays' to those who need them, and is true in so far forth (if
to gain moral holidays be a good), [Footnote: Op. cit., p. 75.] I
offered this as a conciliatory olive-branch to my enemies. But
they, as is only too common with such offerings, trampled the gift
under foot and turned and rent the giver. I had counted too much on
their good will—oh for the rarity of Christian charity under the
sun! Oh for the rarity of ordinary secular intelligence also! I had
supposed it to be matter of common observation that, of two
competing views of the universe which in all other respects are
equal, but of which the first denies some vital human need while
the second satisfies it, the second will be favored by sane men for
the simple reason that it makes the world seem more rational. To
choose the first view under such circumstances would be an ascetic
act, an act of philosophic self-denial of which no normal human
being would be guilty. Using the pragmatic test of the meaning of
concepts, I had shown the concept of the absolute to MEAN nothing
but the holiday giver, the banisher of cosmic fear. One's objective
deliverance, when one says 'the absolute exists,' amounted, on my
showing, just to this, that 'some justification of a feeling of
security in presence of the universe,' exists, and that
systematically to refuse to cultivate a feeling of security would
be to do violence to a tendency in one's emotional life which might
well be respected as prophetic.Apparently my absolutist critics fail to see the workings of
their own minds in any such picture, so all that I can do is to
apologize, and take my offering back. The absolute is true in NO
way then, and least of all, by the verdict of the critics, in the
way which I assigned!My treatment of 'God,' 'freedom,' and 'design' was similar.
Reducing, by the pragmatic test, the meaning of each of these
concepts to its positive experienceable operation, I showed them
all to mean the same thing, viz., the presence of 'promise' in the
world. 'God or no God?' means 'promise or no promise?' It seems to
me that the alternative is objective enough, being a question as to
whether the cosmos has one character or another, even though our
own provisional answer be made on subjective grounds. Nevertheless
christian and non-christian critics alike accuse me of summoning
people to say 'God exists,' EVEN WHEN HE DOESN'T EXIST, because
forsooth in my philosophy the 'truth' of the saying doesn't really
mean that he exists in any shape whatever, but only that to say so
feels good.Most of the pragmatist and anti-pragmatist warfare is over
what the word 'truth' shall be held to signify, and not over any of
the facts embodied in truth-situations; for both pragmatists and
anti-pragmatists believe in existent objects, just as they believe
in our ideas of them. The difference is that when the pragmatists
speak of truth, they mean exclusively some thing about the ideas,
namely their workableness; whereas when anti-pragmatists speak of
truth they seem most often to mean something about the objects.
Since the pragmatist, if he agrees that an idea is 'really' true,
also agrees to whatever it says about its object; and since most
anti-pragmatists have already come round to agreeing that, if the
object exists, the idea that it does so is workable; there would
seem so little left to fight about that I might well be asked why
instead of reprinting my share in so much verbal wrangling, I do
not show my sense of 'values' by burning it all up.I understand the question and I will give my answer. I am
interested in another doctrine in philosophy to which I give the
name of radical empiricism, and it seems to me that the
establishment of the pragmatist theory of truth is a step of
first-rate importance in making radical empiricism prevail. Radical
empiricism consists first of a postulate, next of a statement of
fact, and finally of a generalized conclusion.The postulate is that the only things that shall be debatable
among philosophers shall be things definable in terms drawn from
experience. [Things of an unexperienceable nature may exist ad
libitum, but they form no part of the material for philosophic
debate.]The statement of fact is that the relations between things,
conjunctive as well as disjunctive, are just as much matters of
direct particular experience, neither more so nor less so, than the
things themselves.The generalized conclusion is that therefore the parts of
experience hold together from next to next by relations that are
themselves parts of experience. The directly apprehended universe
needs, in short, no extraneous trans-empirical connective support,
but possesses in its own right a concatenated or continuous
structure.The great obstacle to radical empiricism in the contemporary
mind is the rooted rationalist belief that experience as
immediately given is all disjunction and no conjunction, and that
to make one world out of this separateness, a higher unifying
agency must be there. In the prevalent idealism this agency is
represented as the absolute all-witness which 'relates' things
together by throwing 'categories' over them like a net. The most
peculiar and unique, perhaps, of all these categories is supposed
to be the truth-relation, which connects parts of reality in pairs,
making of one of them a knower, and of the other a thing known, yet
which is itself contentless experientially, neither describable,
explicable, nor reduceable to lower terms, and denotable only by
uttering the name 'truth.'The pragmatist view, on the contrary, of the truth-relation
is that it has a definite content, and that everything in it is
experienceable. Its whole nature can be told in positive terms. The
'workableness' which ideas must have, in order to be true, means
particular workings, physical or intellectual, actual or possible,
which they may set up from next to next inside of concrete
experience. Were this pragmatic contention admitted, one great
point in the victory of radical empiricism would also be scored,
for the relation between an object and the idea that truly knows
it, is held by rationalists to be nothing of this describable sort,
but to stand outside of all possible temporal experience; and on
the relation, so interpreted, rationalism is wonted to make its
last most obdurate rally.Now the anti-pragmatist contentions which I try to meet in
this volume can be so easily used by rationalists as weapons of
resistance, not only to pragmatism but to radical empiricism also
(for if the truth-relation were transcendent, others might be so
too), that I feel strongly the strategical importance of having
them definitely met and got out of the way. What our critics most
persistently keep saying is that though workings go with truth, yet
they do not constitute it. It is numerically additional to them,
prior to them, explanatory OF them, and in no wise to be explained
BY them, we are incessantly told. The first point for our enemies
to establish, therefore, is that SOMETHING numerically additional
and prior to the workings is involved in the truth of an idea.
Since the OBJECT is additional, and usually prior, most
rationalists plead IT, and boldly accuse us of denying it. This
leaves on the bystanders the impression—since we cannot reasonably
deny the existence of the object—that our account of truth breaks
down, and that our critics have driven us from the field. Altho in
various places in this volume I try to refute the slanderous charge
that we deny real existence, I will say here again, for the sake of
emphasis, that the existence of the object, whenever the idea
asserts it 'truly,' is the only reason, in innumerable cases, why
the idea does work successfully, if it work at all; and that it
seems an abuse of language, to say the least, to transfer the word
'truth' from the idea to the object's existence, when the falsehood
of ideas that won't work is explained by that existence as well as
the truth of those that will.I find this abuse prevailing among my most accomplished
adversaries. But once establish the proper verbal custom, let the
word 'truth' represent a property of the idea, cease to make it
something mysteriously connected with the object known, and the
path opens fair and wide, as I believe, to the discussion of
radical empiricism on its merits. The truth of an idea will then
mean only its workings, or that in it which by ordinary
psychological laws sets up those workings; it will mean neither the
idea's object, nor anything 'saltatory' inside the idea, that terms
drawn from experience cannot describe.One word more, ere I end this preface. A distinction is
sometimes made between Dewey, Schiller and myself, as if I, in
supposing the object's existence, made a concession to popular
prejudice which they, as more radical pragmatists, refuse to make.
As I myself understand these authors, we all three absolutely agree
in admitting the transcendency of the object (provided it be an
experienceable object) to the subject, in the truth-relation. Dewey
in particular has insisted almost ad nauseam that the whole meaning
of our cognitive states and processes lies in the way they
intervene in the control and revaluation of independent existences
or facts. His account of knowledge is not only absurd, but
meaningless, unless independent existences be there of which our
ideas take account, and for the transformation of which they work.
But because he and Schiller refuse to discuss objects and relations
'transcendent' in the sense of being ALTOGETHER TRANS-EXPERIENTIAL,
their critics pounce on sentences in their writings to that effect
to show that they deny the existence WITHIN THE REALM OF EXPERIENCE
of objects external to the ideas that declare their presence there.
[Footnote: It gives me pleasure to welcome Professor Carveth Read
into the pragmatistic church, so far as his epistemology goes. See
his vigorous book, The Metaphysics of Nature, 2d Edition, Appendix
A. (London, Black, 1908.) The work What is Reality? by Francis Howe
Johnson (Boston, 1891), of which I make the acquaintance only while
correcting these proofs, contains some striking anticipations of
the later pragmatist view. The Psychology of Thinking, by Irving E.
Miller (New York, Macmillan Co., 1909), which has just appeared, is
one of the most convincing pragmatist document yet published, tho
it does not use the word 'pragmatism' at all. While I am making
references, I cannot refrain from inserting one to the
extraordinarily acute article by H. V. Knox in the Quarterly Review
for April, 1909.]It seems incredible that educated and apparently sincere
critics should so fail to catch their adversary's point of
view.What misleads so many of them is possibly also the fact that
the universes of discourse of Schiller, Dewey, and myself are
panoramas of different extent, and that what the one postulates
explicitly the other provisionally leaves only in a state of
implication, while the reader thereupon considers it to be denied.
Schiller's universe is the smallest, being essentially a
psychological one. He starts with but one sort of thing,
truth-claims, but is led ultimately to the independent objective
facts which they assert, inasmuch as the most successfully
validated of all claims is that such facts are there. My universe
is more essentially epistemological. I start with two things, the
objective facts and the claims, and indicate which claims, the
facts being there, will work successfully as the latter's
substitutes and which will not. I call the former claims true.
Dewey's panorama, if I understand this colleague, is the widest of
the three, but I refrain from giving my own account of its
complexity. Suffice it that he holds as firmly as I do to objects
independent of our judgments. If I am wrong in saying this, he must
correct me. I decline in this matter to be corrected at second
hand.I have not pretended in the following pages to consider all
the critics of my account of truth, such as Messrs. Taylor,
Lovejoy, Gardiner, Bakewell, Creighton, Hibben, Parodi, Salter,
Carus, Lalande, Mentre, McTaggart, G. E. Moore, Ladd and others,
especially not Professor Schinz, who has published under the title
of Anti-pragmatisme an amusing sociological romance. Some of these
critics seem to me to labor under an inability almost pathetic, to
understand the thesis which they seek to refute. I imagine that
most of their difficulties have been answered by anticipation
elsewhere in this volume, and I am sure that my readers will thank
me for not adding more repetition to the fearful amount that is
already there.
I
I
THE FUNCTION OF COGNITION [Footnote: Read before the
Aristotelian Society, December 1, 1884, and first published in
Mind, vol. x (1885).—This, and the following articles have received
a very slight verbal revision, consisting mostly in the omission of
redundancy.]The following inquiry is (to use a distinction familiar to
readers of Mr. Shadworth Hodgson) not an inquiry into the 'how it
comes,' but into the 'what it is' of cognition. What we call acts
of cognition are evidently realized through what we call brains and
their events, whether there be 'souls' dynamically connected with
the brains or not. But with neither brains nor souls has this essay
any business to transact. In it we shall simply assume that
cognition IS produced, somehow, and limit ourselves to asking what
elements it contains, what factors it implies.Cognition is a function of consciousness. The first factor it
implies is therefore a state of consciousness wherein the cognition
shall take place. Having elsewhere used the word 'feeling' to
designate generically all states of consciousness considered
subjectively, or without respect to their possible function, I
shall then say that, whatever elements an act of cognition may
imply besides, it at least implies the existence of a FEELING. [If
the reader share the current antipathy to the word 'feeling,' he
may substitute for it, wherever I use it, the word 'idea,' taken in
the old broad Lockian sense, or he may use the clumsy phrase 'state
of consciousness,' or finally he may say 'thought'
instead.]Now it is to be observed that the common consent of mankind
has agreed that some feelings are cognitive and some are simple
facts having a subjective, or, what one might almost call a
physical, existence, but no such self-transcendent function as
would be implied in their being pieces of knowledge. Our task is
again limited here. We are not to ask, 'How is self-transcendence
possible?' We are only to ask, 'How comes it that common sense has
assigned a number of cases in which it is assumed not only to be
possible but actual? And what are the marks used by common sense to
distinguish those cases from the rest?' In short, our inquiry is a
chapter in descriptive psychology,—hardly anything
more.Condillac embarked on a quest similar to this by his famous
hypothesis of a statue to which various feelings were successively
imparted. Its first feeling was supposed to be one of fragrance.
But to avoid all possible complication with the question of
genesis, let us not attribute even to a statue the possession of
our imaginary feeling. Let us rather suppose it attached to no
matter, nor localized at any point in space, but left swinging IN
VACUO, as it were, by the direct creative FIAT of a god. And let us
also, to escape entanglement with difficulties about the physical
or psychical nature of its 'object' not call it a feeling of
fragrance or of any other determinate sort, but limit ourselves to
assuming that it is a feeling of Q. What is true of it under this
abstract name will be no less true of it in any more particular
shape (such as fragrance, pain, hardness) which the reader may
suppose.Now, if this feeling of Q be the only creation of the god, it
will of course form the entire universe. And if, to escape the
cavils of that large class of persons who believe that SEMPER IDEM
SENTIRE AC NON SENTIRE are the same, [Footnote:1 'The Relativity of
Knowledge,' held in this sense, is, it may be observed in passing,
one of the oddest of philosophic superstitions. Whatever facts may
be cited in its favor are due to the properties of nerve-tissue,
which may be exhausted by too prolonged an excitement. Patients
with neuralgias that last unremittingly for days can, however,
assure us that the limits of this nerve-law are pretty widely
drawn. But if we physically could get a feeling that should last
eternally unchanged, what atom of logical or psychological argument
is there to prove that it would not be felt as long as it lasted,
and felt for just what it is, all that time? The reason for the
opposite prejudice seems to be our reluctance to think that so
stupid a thing as such a feeling would necessarily be, should be
allowed to fill eternity with its presence. An interminable
acquaintance, leading to no knowledge-about,—such would be its
condition.] we allow the feeling to be of as short a duration as
they like, that universe will only need to last an infinitesimal
part of a second. The feeling in question will thus be reduced to
its fighting weight, and all that befalls it in the way of a
cognitive function must be held to befall in the brief instant of
its quickly snuffed-out life,—a life, it will also be noticed, that
has no other moment of consciousness either preceding or following
it.Well now, can our little feeling, thus left alone in the
universe,—for the god and we psychological critics may be supposed
left out of the account,—can the feeling, I say, be said to have
any sort of a cognitive function? For it to KNOW, there must be
something to be known. What is there, on the present supposition?
One may reply, 'the feeling's content q.' But does it not seem more
proper to call this the feeling's QUALITY than its content? Does
not the word 'content' suggest that the feeling has already
dirempted itself as an act from its content as an object? And would
it be quite safe to assume so promptly that the quality q of a
feeling is one and the same thing with a feeling of the quality q?
The quality q, so far, is an entirely subjective fact which the
feeling carries so to speak endogenously, or in its pocket. If any
one pleases to dignify so simple a fact as this by the name of
knowledge, of course nothing can prevent him. But let us keep
closer to the path of common usage, and reserve the name knowledge
for the cognition of 'realities,' meaning by realities things that
exist independently of the feeling through which their cognition
occurs. If the content of the feeling occur nowhere in the universe
outside of the feeling itself, and perish with the feeling, common
usage refuses to call it a reality, and brands it as a subjective
feature of the feeling's constitution, or at the most as the
feeling's DREAM.For the feeling to be cognitive in the specific sense, then,
it must be self-transcendent; and we must prevail upon the god to
CREATE A REALITY OUTSIDE OF IT to correspond to its intrinsic
quality Q. Thus only can it be redeemed from the condition of being
a solipsism. If now the new created reality RESEMBLE the feeling's
quality Q I say that the feeling may be held by us TO BE COGNIZANT
OF THAT REALITY.This first instalment of my thesis is sure to be attacked.
But one word before defending it 'Reality' has become our warrant
for calling a feeling cognitive; but what becomes our warrant for
calling anything reality? The only reply is—the faith of the
present critic or inquirer. At every moment of his life he finds
himself subject to a belief in SOME realities, even though his
realities of this year should prove to be his illusions of the
next. Whenever he finds that the feeling he is studying
contemplates what he himself regards as a reality, he must of
course admit the feeling itself to be truly cognitive. We are
ourselves the critics here; and we shall find our burden much
lightened by being allowed to take reality in this relative and
provisional way. Every science must make some assumptions.
Erkenntnisstheoretiker are but fallible mortals. When they study
the function of cognition, they do it by means of the same function
in themselves. And knowing that the fountain cannot go higher than
its source, we should promptly confess that our results in this
field are affected by our own liability to err. THE MOST WE CAN
CLAIM IS, THAT WHAT WE SAY ABOUT COGNITION MAY BE COUNTED AS TRUE
AS WHAT WE SAY ABOUT ANYTHING ELSE. If our hearers agree with us
about what are to be held 'realities,' they will perhaps also agree
to the reality of our doctrine of the way in which they are known.
We cannot ask for more.Our terminology shall follow the spirit of these remarks. We
will deny the function of knowledge to any feeling whose quality or
content we do not ourselves believe to exist outside of that
feeling as well as in it. We may call such a feeling a dream if we
like; we shall have to see later whether we can call it a fiction
or an error.To revert now to our thesis. Some persons will immediately
cry out, 'How CAN a reality resemble a feeling?' Here we find how
wise we were to name the quality of the feeling by an algebraic
letter Q. We flank the whole difficulty of resemblance between an
inner state and an outward reality, by leaving it free to any one
to postulate as the reality whatever sort of thing he thinks CAN
resemble a feeling,—if not an outward thing, then another feeling
like the first one,—the mere feeling Q in the critic's mind for
example. Evading thus this objection, we turn to another which is
sure to be urged.It will come from those philosophers to whom 'thought,' in
the sense of a knowledge of relations, is the all in all of mental
life; and who hold a merely feeling consciousness to be no
better—one would sometimes say from their utterances, a good deal
worse—than no consciousness at all. Such phrases as these, for
example, are common to-day in the mouths of those who claim to walk
in the footprints of Kant and Hegel rather than in the ancestral
English paths: 'A perception detached from all others, "left out of
the heap we call a mind," being out of all relation, has no
qualities—is simply nothing. We can no more consider it than we can
see vacancy.' 'It is simply in itself fleeting, momentary,
unnameable (because while we name it it has become another), and
for the very same reason unknowable, the very negation of
knowability.' 'Exclude from what we have considered real all
qualities constituted by relation, we find that none are
left.'Altho such citations as these from the writings of Professor
Green might be multiplied almost indefinitely, they would hardly
repay the pains of collection, so egregiously false is the doctrine
they teach. Our little supposed feeling, whatever it may be, from
the cognitive point of view, whether a bit of knowledge or a dream,
is certainly no psychical zero. It is a most positively and
definitely qualified inner fact, with a complexion all its own. Of
course there are many mental facts which it is NOT. It knows Q, if
Q be a reality, with a very minimum of knowledge. It neither dates
nor locates it. It neither classes nor names it. And it neither
knows itself as a feeling, nor contrasts itself with other
feelings, nor estimates its own duration or intensity. It is, in
short, if there is no more of it than this, a most dumb and
helpless and useless kind of thing.But if we must describe it by so many negations, and if it
can say nothing ABOUT itself or ABOUT anything else, by what right
do we deny that it is a psychical zero? And may not the
'relationists' be right after all?In the innocent looking word 'about' lies the solution of
this riddle; and a simple enough solution it is when frankly looked
at. A quotation from a too seldom quoted book, the Exploratio
Philosophica of John Grote (London, 1865), p. 60, will form the
best introduction to it.'Our knowledge,' writes Grote, 'may be contemplated in either
of two ways, or, to use other words, we may speak in a double
manner of the "object" of knowledge. That is, we may either use
language thus: we KNOW a thing, a man, etc.; or we may use it thus:
we know such and such things ABOUT the thing, the man, etc.
Language in general, following its true logical instinct,
distinguishes between these two applications of the notion of
knowledge, the one being yvwvai, noscere, kennen, connaitre, the
other being eidevai, scire, wissen, savoir. In the origin, the
former may be considered more what I have called phenomenal—it is
the notion of knowledge as ACQUAINTANCE or familiarity with what is
known; which notion is perhaps more akin to the phenomenal bodily
communication, and is less purely intellectual than the other; it
is the kind of knowledge which we have of a thing by the
presentation to the senses or the representation of it in picture
or type, a Vorstellung. The other, which is what we express in
judgments or propositions, what is embodied in Begriffe or concepts
without any necessary imaginative representation, is in its origin
the more intellectual notion of knowledge. There is no reason,
however, why we should not express our knowledge, whatever its
kind, in either manner, provided only we do not confusedly express
it, in the same proposition or piece of reasoning, in
both.'Now obviously if our supposed feeling of Q is (if knowledge
at all) only knowledge of the mere acquaintance-type, it is milking
a he-goat, as the ancients would have said, to try to extract from
it any deliverance ABOUT anything under the sun, even about itself.
And it is as unjust, after our failure, to turn upon it and call it
a psychical nothing, as it would be, after our fruitless attack
upon the billy-goat, to proclaim the non-lactiferous character of
the whole goat-tribe. But the entire industry of the Hegelian
school in trying to shove simple sensation out of the pale of
philosophic recognition is founded on this false issue. It is
always the 'speechlessness' of sensation, its inability to make any
'statement,'[Footnote: See, for example, Green's Introduction to
Hume's Treatise of Human Nature, p. 36.] that is held to make the
very notion of it meaningless, and to justify the student of
knowledge in scouting it out of existence. 'Significance,' in the
sense of standing as the sign of other mental states, is taken to
be the sole function of what mental states we have; and from the
perception that our little primitive sensation has as yet no
significance in this literal sense, it is an easy step to call it
first meaningless, next senseless, then vacuous, and finally to
brand it as absurd and inadmissible. But in this universal
liquidation, this everlasting slip, slip, slip, of direct
acquaintance into knowledge-ABOUT, until at last nothing is left
about which the knowledge can be supposed to obtain, does not all
'significance' depart from the situation? And when our knowledge
about things has reached its never so complicated perfection, must
there not needs abide alongside of it and inextricably mixed in
with it some acquaintance with WHAT things all this knowledge is
about?Now, our supposed little feeling gives a WHAT; and if other
feelings should succeed which remember the first, its WHAT may
stand as subject or predicate of some piece of knowledge-about, of
some judgment, perceiving relations between it and other WHATS
which the other feelings may know. The hitherto dumb Q will then
receive a name and be no longer speechless. But every name, as
students of logic know, has its 'denotation'; and the denotation
always means some reality or content, relationless as extra or with
its internal relations unanalyzed, like the Q which our primitive
sensation is supposed to know. No relation-expressing proposition
is possible except on the basis of a preliminary acquaintance with
such 'facts,' with such contents, as this. Let the Q be fragrance,
let it be toothache, or let it be a more complex kind of feeling,
like that of the full-moon swimming in her blue abyss, it must
first come in that simple shape, and be held fast in that first
intention, before any knowledge ABOUT it can be attained. The
knowledge ABOUT it is IT with a context added. Undo IT, and what is
added cannot be CONtext. [Footnote: If A enters and B exclaims,
'Didn't you see my brother on the stairs?' we all hold that A may
answer, 'I saw him, but didn't know he was your brother'; ignorance
of brotherhood not abolishing power to see. But those who, on
account of the unrelatedness of the first facts with which we
become acquainted, deny them to be 'known' to us, ought in
consistency to maintain that if A did not perceive the relationship
of the man on the stairs to B, it was impossible he should have
noticed him at all.]