After Life in Roman Paganism
After Life in Roman PaganismPREFACEHISTORICAL INTRODUCTIONI AFTER LIFE IN THE TOMBII THE NETHER WORLDIII CELESTIAL IMMORTALITYIV THE WINNING OF IMMORTALITYV UNTIMELY DEATHVI THE JOURNEY TO THE BEYONDVII THE SUFFERINGS OF HELL AND METEMPSYCHOSISVIII THE FELICITY OF THE BLESSEDNotesCopyright
After Life in Roman Paganism
Franz Valery Marie Cumont
PREFACE
At the invitation of the President of Yale University and of
Professor Russell H. Chittenden, chairman of the committee in
charge of the Silliman Foundation, the lectures which are here
presented to a wider public were delivered in New Haven during the
month of March of the year 1921. It was the wish of the committee
that I should speak upon some subject from the history of religion.
I chose therefore as my theme a matter which had occupied my
attention for many years, viz., the ideas current in Roman paganism
concerning the lot of the soul after death. The argument has been
treated more than once by distinguished scholars and notably—to
mention only an English book—by Mrs. Arthur Strong in her recent
work “Apotheosis and After Life,” a study characterised by
penetrating interpretation, especially of archaeological monuments.
But we do not yet possess for the Roman imperial epoch a
counterpart to Rohde’s classical volume, “Psyche,” for the earlier
Greek period, that is, a work in which the whole evolution of Roman
belief and speculation regarding a future life is set forth. These
lectures cannot claim to fill this gap. They may however be looked
upon as a sketch of the desired investigation, in which, though
without the detailed citation of supporting evidence, an attempt at
least has been made to trace the broad outlines of the subject in
all its magnitude.The lectures are printed in the form in which they were
delivered. The necessity of making each one intelligible to an
audience which was not always the same, has made inevitable some
repetitions. Cross references have been added, where the same
topics are treated in different connections. However, in a book
intended primarily for the general reader, the scholarly apparatus
has been reduced to a minimum and as a rule indicates only the
source of passages quoted in the text.My acknowledgment is due to Miss Helen Douglas Irvine, who
with skill and intelligent understanding of the subject translated
into English the French text of these lectures. I wish also to
express my gratitude to my friends, Professor George Lincoln
Hendrickson, who took upon himself the tedious task of reading the
manuscript and the proofs of this book and to whom I am indebted
for many valuable suggestions both in matter and in form, and
Professor Grant Showerman, who obligingly consented to revise the
last chapters before they were printed.Rome, September, 1922.
HISTORICAL INTRODUCTION
The idea of death has perhaps never been more present to
humanity than during the years through which we have just passed.
It has been the daily companion of millions of men engaged in a
murderous conflict; it has haunted the even larger number who have
trembled for the lives of their nearest and dearest; it is still
constantly in the thoughts of the many who nurse regret for those
they loved. And doubtless also, the faith or the hope has never
more imposed itself, even on the unbelieving, that these countless
multitudes, filled with moral force and generous passion, who have
entered eternity, have not wholly perished, that the ardour which
animated them was not extinguished when their limbs grew cold, that
the spirit which impelled them to self-sacrifice was not dissipated
with the atoms which formed their bodies.These feelings were known to the ancients also, who gave to
this very conviction the form suggested by their religion.
Pericles[1]in his
funeral eulogy of the warriors who fell at the siege of Samos
declared that they who die for their country become like the
immortal gods, and that, invisible like them, they still scatter
their benefits on us. The ideas on immortality held in antiquity
are often thus at once far from and near to our own—nearbecause they correspond to
aspirations which are not antique or modern, but human,farbecause the Olympians now have
fallen into the deep gulf where lie dethroned deities. These ideas
become more and more like the conceptions familiar to us as
gradually their time grows later, and those generally admitted at
the end of paganism are analogous to the doctrines accepted
throughout the Middle Ages.I flatter myself, therefore, that when I speak to you of the
beliefs in a future life held in Roman times I have chosen a
subject which is not very remote from us nor such as has no
relation to our present thought or is capable of interesting only
the learned.We can here trace only the outlines of this vast subject. I
am aware that it is always imprudent to hazard moral
generalisations: they are always wrong somewhere. Above all, it is
perilous to attempt to determine with a few words the infinite
variety of individual creeds, for nothing escapes historical
observation more easily than the intimate convictions of men, which
they often hide even from those near them. In periods of scepticism
pious souls cling to old beliefs; the conservative crowd remains
faithful to ancestral traditions. When religion is resuming its
empire, rationalistic minds resist the contagion of faith. It is
especially difficult to ascertain up to what point ideas adopted by
intellectual circles succeeded in penetrating the deep masses of
the people. The epitaphs which have been preserved give us too
scanty and too sparse evidence in this particular. Besides, in
paganism a dogma does not necessarily exclude its opposite dogma:
the two sometimes persist side by side in one mind as different
possibilities, each of which is authorised by a respectable
tradition. You will therefore make the necessary reservations to
such of my statements as are too absolute. I shall be able to point
out here only the great spiritual currents which successively
brought to Rome new ideas as to the Beyond, and to sketch the
evolution undergone by the doctrines as to the lot and the abode of
souls. You will not expect me to be precise as to the number of the
partisans of each of these doctrines in the various
periods.At least we can distinguish the principal phases of the
religious movement which caused imperial society to pass from
incredulity to certain forms of belief in immortality, forms at
first somewhat crude but afterwards loftier, and we can see where
this movement led. The change was a capital one and transformed for
the ancients the whole conception of life. The axis about which
morality revolved had to be shifted when ethics no longer sought,
as in earlier Greek philosophy, to realise the sovereign good on
this earth but looked for it after death. Thenceforth the activity
of man aimed less at tangible realities, ensuring well-being to the
family or the city or the state, and more at attaining to the
fulfilment of ideal hopes in a supernatural world. Our sojourn here
below was conceived as a preparation for another existence, as a
transitory trial which was to result in infinite felicity or
suffering. Thus the table of ethical values was turned upside
down.
“ All our actions and all our thoughts,” says Pascal, “must
follow so different a course if there are eternal possessions for
which we may hope than if there are not, that it is impossible to
take any directed and well-judged step except by regulating it in
view of this point which ought to be our ultimate goal.”[2]We will attempt first to sketch in a general introduction the
historical transformation which belief in the future life underwent
between the Republican period and the fall of paganism. Then, in
three lectures, we will examine more closely the various
conceptions of the abode of the dead held under the Roman Empire,
study in three others the conditions or the means which enable men
to attain to immortality and in the last two set forth the lot of
souls in the Beyond.The cinerary vases of the prehistoric period are often
modelled in the shape of huts: throughout, funeral sculpture
follows the tradition that the tomb should reproduce the dwelling,
and until the end of antiquity it was designated, in the West as in
the East, as the “eternal house” of him who rested in
it.Thus a conception of the tomb which goes back to the remotest
ages and persists through the centuries regards it as “the last
dwelling” of those who have left us; and this expression has not
yet gone out of use. It was believed that a dead man continued to
live, in the narrow space granted him, a life which was groping,
obscure, precarious, yet like that he led on earth. Subject to the
same needs, obliged to eat and to drink, he expected those who had
been nearest to him to appease his hunger and thirst. The utensils
he had used, the things he had cared for, were often deposited
beside him so that he might pursue the occupations and enjoy the
amusements which he had forsaken in the world. If he were satisfied
he would stay quietly in the furnished house provided for him and
would not seek to avenge himself on those whose neglect had caused
him suffering. Funeral rites were originally inspired rather by
fear than by love. They were precautions taken against the spirit
of the dead rather than pious care bestowed in their
interest.[3]For the dead were powerful; their action was still felt; they
were not immured in the tomb or confined beneath the ground. Men
saw them reappear in dreams, wearing their former aspect. They were
descried during shadowy vigils; their voices were heard and their
movements noted. Imagination conceived them such as they had once
been; recollection of them filled the memory and to think of such
apparitions as idle or unreal seemed impossible. The dead
subsisted, then, as nebulous, impalpable beings, perceived by the
senses only exceptionally. Here the belief that their remains had
not quite lost all feeling mingled with the equally primitive and
universal belief that the soul is a breath, exhaled with the last
sigh. The vaporous shade, sometimes a dangerous but sometimes a
succouring power, wandered by night in the atmosphere and haunted
the places which the living man had been used to frequent. Except
for some sceptical reasoners, all antiquity admitted the reality of
these phantoms. Century-old beliefs, maintained by traditional
rites, thus persisted, more or less definitely, in the popular
mind, even after new forms of the future life were imagined. Many
vestiges of these beliefs have survived until today.The first transformation undergone by the primitive
conception was to entertain the opinion that the dead who are
deposited in the ground gather together in a great cavity inside
the bowels of the earth.[4]This
belief in the nether world is found among most of the peoples of
the Mediterranean basin: theSheolof the Hebrews differs little from the HomericHadesand the ItalicInferi.It has been conjectured that the substitution of incineration
for inhumation contributed to spreading this new manner of
conceiving life beyond the tomb: the shade could not remain
attached to a handful of ashes enclosed in a puny urn. It went,
then, to join its fellows who had gone down into the dark dwelling
where reigned the gods of a subterranean kingdom. But as ghosts
could leave their graves in order to trouble or to help men, so the
swarms of the infernal spirits rose to the upper world through the
natural openings of the earth, or through ditches dug for the
purpose of maintaining communication with them and conciliating
them with offerings.The Romans do not seem to have imagined survival in the
infernal regions very differently from the survival of the vague
monotonous shades in their tombs. TheirManesorLemureshad no marked personality or
clearly characterised individual features. TheInferiwere not, as in Greece, a stage
for the enactment of a tragic drama; their inhabitants had no
original life, and in the lot dealt to them no idea of retribution
can be discerned. In this matter it was the Hellenes who imposed
their conceptions of Hades on the Italic peoples and gave them
those half mythical and half theological beliefs which Orphism had
introduced in their own religion. Hellenic influence was felt
directly through the colonies of Greater Greece, indirectly through
the Etruscans, whose funeral sculpture shows us that they had
adopted all the familiar figures of the Greek Hades—Charon,
Cerberus, the Furies, Hermes Psychopompos and the others.[5]From the time when Latin literature had its beginnings and
the Latin theatre was born, we find writers taking pleasure in
reproducing the Hellenic fables of Tartarus and the Elysian Fields;
and Plautus[6]can
already make one of his characters say that he has seen “many
paintings representing the pains of Acheron.” This infernal
mythology became an inexhaustible theme which gave matter to poetry
and art until the end of antiquity and beyond it. We shall see, in
later lectures, how the religious traditions of the Greeks were
subjected to various transformations and
interpretations.But Greece did not introduce poetic beliefs only into Rome:
she also caused her philosophy to be adopted there from the second
century onwards, and this philosophy tended to be destructive both
of those beliefs and of the old native faith in the Manes and in
the Orcus. Polybius,[7]when
speaking appreciatively of the religion of the Romans, praises them
for having inculcated in the people a faith in numerous
superstitious practices and tragic fictions. He considers this to
be an excellent way of keeping them to their duty by the fear of
infernal punishment. Hence we gather that if the historian thought
it well for the people to believe in these inventions, then, in his
opinion, enlightened persons, like his friends the Scipios, could
see in them nothing but the stratagems of a prudent policy. But the
scepticism of a narrow circle of aristocrats could not be confined
to it for long when Greek ideas were more widely
propagated.Greek philosophy made an early attack on the ideas held as to
a future life. Even Democritus, the forerunner of Epicurus, spoke
of “some people who ignore the dissolution of our mortal nature
and, aware of the perversity of their life, pass their time in
unrest and in fear and forge for themselves deceitful fables as to
the time when follows their end.”[8]It is
true that in the fourth century Plato’s idealism had supplied, if
not a strict proof of immortality, yet reasons for it sufficient to
procure its acceptance by such as desired to be convinced. But in
the Alexandrian age, which was the surpassingly scientific period
of Greek thought, there was a tendency to remove all metaphysical
and mythical conceptions of the soul’s destiny from the field of
contemplation. This was the period in which the Academy, Plato’s
own school, unfaithful to its founder’s doctrines, was led by men
who, like Carneades, raised scepticism to a system and stated that
man can reach no certainty. We know that when Carneades was sent to
Rome as ambassador in 156 B. C. he made a great impression by
maintaining that justice is a matter of convention, and that he was
consequently banished by the senate as a danger to the state. But
we need only read Cicero’s works to learn what a lasting influence
his powerfully destructive dialectics had.The dogmatism of other sects was at this time hardly at all
more favourable to the traditional beliefs in another
life.Aristotle had thought that human reason alone persisted, and
that the emotional and nutritive soul was destroyed with the body,
but he left no personality to this pure intelligence, deprived of
all sensibility. He definitely denied that the “blessed” could be
happy. With him begins a long period during which Greek philosophy
nearly ceased to speculate on destiny beyond the grave. It was
repugnant to Peripatetic philosophy to concern itself with the
existence of a soul which could be neither conceived nor defined by
reason. Some of Aristotle’s immediate disciples, like Aristoxenus
and Dicaearchus, or Straton of Lampsacus, the pupil of
Theophrastus, agreed in denying immortality altogether; and later,
in the time of the Severi, Alexander of Aphrodisias, the great
commentator of The Stagirite, undertook to prove that the entire
soul, that is the higher and the lower soul, had need of the body
in order to be active and perished with it, and that such was the
veritable thought of the master. But profoundly as Peripateticism
affected Greek thought, directly and indirectly, in practically
discarding the future life, this was not the philosophy which
dominated minds towards the end of the Roman Republic. Other
schools then had a much wider influence and made this influence
felt much more deeply on eschatological beliefs. These schools were
Epicureanism and Stoicism.Epicurus took up again the doctrine of Democritus, and taught
that the soul, which was composed of atoms, was disintegrated at
the moment of death, when it was no longer held together by its
fleshly wrapping, and that its transitory unity was then destroyed
for ever. The vital breath, after being expelled, was, he said,
buffeted by the winds and dissolved in the air like mist or smoke,
even before the body was decomposed. This was so ancient a
conception that Homer had made use of a like comparison, and the
idea that the violence of the wind can act on souls as a
destructive force was familiar to Athenian children in Plato’s
time.[9]But if
the soul thus resolves itself, after death, into its elementary
principles, how can phantoms come to frighten us in the watches of
the night or beloved beings visit us in our dreams? These simulacra
(εἴδωλα) are for Epicurus no more than emanations of particles of
an extreme tenuity, constantly issuing from bodies and keeping for
some time their form and appearance. They act on our senses as do
colour and scent and awake in us the image of a vanished
being.Thus we are vowed to annihilation, but this lot is not one to
be dreaded. Death, which is held to be the most horrible of ills,
is in reality nothing of the sort, since the destruction of our
organism abolishes all its sensibility. The time when we no longer
exist is no more painful for us than that when we had not yet our
being. As Plato deduced the persistence of the soul after death
from its supposed previous existence, so Epicurus drew an opposite
conclusion from our ignorance of our earlier life; and, according
to him, the conviction that we perish wholly can alone ensure our
tranquillity of spirit by delivering us from the fear of eternal
torment.There is no one of the master’s doctrines on which his
disciples insist with more complacent assurance. They praise him
for having freed men from the terrors of the Beyond; they thank him
for having taught them not to fear death; his philosophy appears to
them as a liberator of souls. Lucretius in his third book, of which
eighteenth-century philosophers delighted to celebrate the merits,
claims, with a sort of exaltation, to drive from men’s hearts “that
dread of Acheron which troubles human life to its inmost
depths.”[10]The
sage sees all the cruel fictions, with which fable had peopled the
kingdom of terrors, scattered abroad, and, when he has rid himself
of the dismay which haunts the common man, which casts a mournful
veil over things and leaves no joy unmixed, he finds a blessed
calm, the perfect quietude or “ataraxia.”This doctrine, which Lucretius preached with the enthusiasm
of a neophyte won to the true faith, had a profound reaction in
Rome. Its adepts in Cicero’s circle were numerous, including
Cassius, the murderer of Caesar. Sallust goes so far as to make
Caesar himself affirm, in full senate, that death, the rest from
torment, dispels the ills which afflict mankind, that beyond it
there is neither joy nor sorrow.[11]Men of
science, in particular, were attracted by these theories. In a
celebrated passage Pliny the Naturalist, after categorically
declaring that neither the soul nor the body has any more sensation
after death than before the day of birth, ends with a vehement
apostrophe: “Unhappy one, what folly is thine who in death renewest
life! Where will creatures ever find rest if souls in heaven, if
shades in the infernal regions, still have feeling? Through this
complacent credulity we lose death, the greatest boon which belongs
to our nature, and the sufferings of our last hour are doubled by
the fear of what will follow after. If it be indeed sweet to live,
for whom can it be so to have lived? How much easier and more
certain is the belief which each man can draw from his own
experience, when he pictures his future tranquillity on the pattern
of that which preceded his birth!”[12]Even Seneca in one of his tragedies, an early work, makes the
chorus of Trojan women declaim a long profession of faith which is
the purest Epicureanism.[13]The invasion of the Roman world by the Oriental mysteries and
superstitions in the second century caused the unbelievers to exalt
Epicurus yet higher. The satirist Lucian, using almost the same
expressions as Lucretius, proclaims the truly sacred and divine
character of him who alone knew the good with the true, and who
transmitted it to his disciples, to whom he gave moral
liberty.[14]Believers everywhere looked upon him as a terrible
blasphemer. The prophet Alexander of Abonotichos enjoined all who
would obtain divine graces to drive away with stones “atheists,
Epicureans and Christians,” and exclude them from his
mysteries.[15]He
ordered by an oracle that the writings of him whom he called “the
blind old man” should be burnt. When mysticism and Platonism
triumphed in the Roman world, Epicureanism ceased to exist. It had
disappeared in the middle of the fourth century, yet Julian the
Apostate thought it advisable to include the writings of Epicurus
among the books which were forbidden to the priests of his revived
paganism.[16]Thus during several centuries this philosophy had won a
multitude of followers. The inscriptions bear eloquent witness to
this fact. The most remarkable of them is a long text which was set
out on the wall of a portico in the little town of Oenoanda in
Lycia. A worthy citizen, Diogenes by name, who seems to have lived
under the Antonines, was a convinced partisan of the doctrine of
Epicurus; and feeling his end draw near, he wished to engrave an
exposition thereof on marble for the present and future edification
of his countrymen and of strangers. He does not fail to evince his
contempt for death, at which, he says, he has learnt to mock. “I do
not let myself be frightened by the Tityi and the Tantali whom some
represent in Hades; horror does not seize me when I think of the
putrefaction of my body ... when the links which bind our organism
are loosened, nothing further touches us.”[17]These
are ideas which we find reproduced everywhere, in various forms,
for Epicureanism did not only win convinced partisans in the most
cultivated circles, but also spread in the lowest strata of the
population, as is proved by epitaphs expressing unbelief in an
after life. Some do not go beyond a short profession of faith, “We
are mortal; we are not immortal.”[18]One
maxim is repeated so often that it is sometimes expressed only by
initials, “I was not; I was; I am not; I do not care.”[19]So man goes back to nothingness whence he went forth. It has
been remarked that this epigraphic formula was engraved especially
on the tombs of slaves, who had slight reason for attachment to
life. Gladiators also adopted the sentence: these wretched men, who
were to prove their indifference to death in the arena, were taught
that it marked the destruction of feeling and the term of their
suffering.The same thought is sometimes expressed less brutally, almost
touchingly. Thus a comedian, who has spouted many verses and
tramped many roads, voices in his epitaph the conviction that life
is a loan, like a part in a play: “My mouth no longer gives out any
sound; the noise of applause no longer reaches me; I paid my debt
to nature and have departed. All this is but dust.”[20]Another
actor, who recited Homer’s verses in the festivals, tells us that
he “laughs at illusions and slumbers softly,” returning to the
Epicurean comparison of death with an unconscious sleep which has
no awakening.[21]Some wordier unbelievers felt the need of enlarging on their
negations.[22]“There
is no boat of Hades, no ferryman Charon, no Aeacus as doorkeeper,
no dog Cerberus. All we, whom death sends down to the earth, become
bones and ashes and no more.... Offer not perfumes and garlands to
my stele: it is but a stone; burn no fire: the expenditure is vain.
If thou have a gift, give it me while I live. If thou givest to my
ashes to drink, thou wilt make mud: and the dead will not drink....
When thou scatterest earth on my remains, say that I have again
become as I was when I was not.” This last thought occurs
frequently. Thus on a Roman tomb we read: “We are and we were
nothing. See, reader, how swiftly we mortals go back from
nothingness to nothingness.”[23]Sometimes these dead adopt a joking tone which is almost
macabre. Thus a freedman, merry to the grave, boasts of the
amenities of his new state: “What remains of man, my bones, rests
sweetly here. I no longer have the fear of sudden starvation; I am
exempt from attacks of gout; my body is no longer pledged for my
rent; and I enjoy free and perpetual hospitality.”[24]Often a grosser Epicureanism recommends that we make profit
of our earthly passage since the fatal term deprives us for ever of
the pleasures which are the sovereign good. “Es bibe lude
veni”—“Eat, drink, play, come hither”—is advice which is several
times repeated.[25]Not
uncommonly, variations occur, inspired by the famous epitaph which
was on the alleged tomb of Sardanapalus and is resumed in the
admonition: “Indulge in voluptuousness, for only this pleasure wilt
thou carry away with thee”; or as it is expressed in the Epistle to
the Corinthians, “Let us eat and drink, for tomorrow we
die.”[26]So we
read on a stone found near Beneventum: “What I have eaten and what
I have drunk; that is all that belongs to me.”[27]A
well-known distich states that “Baths, wine, and love impair our
bodies, but baths, wine, and love make life”;[28]and a
veteran of the army had advice based on his own example engraved on
his tomb, “While I lived, I drank willingly; drink, ye who
live.”[29]The
exhortation to enjoy a life soon to be interrupted by death is a
traditional theme which has lent itself to many developments in
ancient and modern poetry. It is the formula which resumes the
wisdom of the popular Epicureanism. Some silver goblets, found in
Boscoreale near Pompeii,[30]show us
philosophers and poets among skeletons, and inscriptions urging
them to rejoice while they live, since no man is certain of the
morrow. Epicurus appears in person, his hand stretching towards a
cake on a table; and between his legs is a little pig lifting his
feet and snout to the cake to take his share of it. Above the cake
are the Greek words, ΤΟ ΤΕΛΟΣ ΗΔΟΝΗ, “The supreme end is pleasure.”
Horace, when he advises us to live from day to day without
poisoning the passing hour with hopes or fears for the future,
speaks of himself, jestingly, as a fat “hog of Epicurus’
herd.”[31]It was
thus that the vulgar interpreted the precepts of him who had in
reality preached moderation and renunciation as the means of
reaching true happiness.If Epicureanism chose its ground as the passionate adversary
of religious beliefs, the other great system which shared its
dominance of minds in Rome, Stoicism, sought, on the contrary, to
reconcile these beliefs with its theories. But the allegorical
interpretations which Stoicism suggested, led, indirectly, to
nearly the same result as a complete negation, for when it changed
the meaning of the ancient myths it really destroyed the traditions
which it sought to preserve. This is true in particular of its
ideas as to the future life.It will be remembered that man is for the Stoics a microcosm,
who reproduces in his person the constitution of the universe. The
entire mass of the world is conceived by them as animated by a
divine Fire, a first principle which evokes the succession of
natural phenomena. An uninterrupted chain of causes, ordered by
this supreme reason, necessarily determines the course of events
and irresistibly governs the existence of the great All. This
cosmic life is conceived as formed of an infinite series of exactly
similar cycles: the four elements are periodically reabsorbed into
the purest of their number, which is the Fire of intelligence, and
then, after the general conflagration, are once more
dissociated.In the same way our organism lives, moves and thinks because
it is animated by a detached particle of this fiery principle which
penetrates everything. As this principle reaches to the limits of
the universe, so our soul occupies the whole body in which it
lodges. The pantheism of the Porch conceives as material both God
and the reason which rules us, the reason which is, in the emphatic
words of Epictetus,[32]“a
fragment of God.” It is defined as a hot breath (πνεῦμα
πυρῶδες,anima inflammata); it
is like the purest part of the air which maintains life by
respiration, or the ardent ether which feeds the stars. This
individual soul maintains and preserves man, as the soul of the
world, by connecting its various parts, saves it from
disintegration. But on both sides this action is only temporary;
souls cannot escape the fatal lot imposed on the whole of which
they are but a tiny portion. At the end of each cosmic period the
universal conflagration (ἐκπύρωσις) will cause them to return to
the divine home whence all of them came forth.[33]But if
the new cycle, making its new beginning, is to reproduce exactly
that which preceded it, a “palingenesis” will one day give to the
same souls, endowed with the same qualities, the same existence in
the same bodies formed of the same elements.This is the maximum limit of the immortality which the
materialistic pantheism of the Stoic philosophy could concede. Nor
did all the doctors agree in granting it. The variations of the
school on a point which seems to us of capital importance are most
remarkable. While Cleanthes did indeed admit that all souls thus
subsisted after their brief passage on earth for thousands of years
and until the finalekpyrosis,
for Chrysippus only the souls of the sages had part in this
restricted immortality. In order to win it they must temper their
strength by resisting the passions. The weak, who had let
themselves be conquered in the struggle of this life, fell in the
Beyond also.[34]At the
most they obtained a short period of after life. The brevity or the
absence of this other existence was the chastisement of their
weakness.Thus, almost the same moral consequences and incitements to
good could be drawn from a conditional and diminished immortality,
as from the general eternity of pains and rewards which other
thinkers taught. But the Stoics were not unanimous in adopting
these doctrines. We do not clearly perceive how far they agreed in
admitting that the soul, deprived of corporeal organs, was endowed
with feeling and, in particular, kept an individual conscience
connected with that possessed on earth. It is certain that a
definitely negative tendency showed itself in Rome among the
sectaries of Zeno. Panaetius, the friend of the Scipios, and one of
the writers who did most to win the Romans over to the ideas of the
Porch, here dissociated himself from his masters and absolutely
denied personal survival.[35]This
attitude was subsequently that of many Roman Stoics of those who
represented the school’s tradition most purely. The master of the
poet Persius, Cornutus, of whom a short work remains to us,
declared that the soul died with the body, immediately.[36]Similarly, at a later date, Epictetus and Marcus Aurelius,
although they sometimes seem to admit the possibility of survival,
certainly incline rather to believe that souls are disintegrated
and return to the elemental mass whence they were formed. Even
Seneca, who is more swayed by other tendencies and whose wavering
thought does not always remain consistent nor perspicuous, is not
convinced of the truth of immortality. It is no more to him than a
beautiful hope.How is it that Stoicism thus hesitated at a point on which
the whole conception of human life seems to us to depend? It was
that eschatological theories had in reality only a secondary value
in this system, of which the essential part was not affected by
their variability. True Stoicism placed the realisation of its
ideal in this world. For it the aim of our existence here below was
not preparation for death but the conquest of perfect virtue, which
freed him who had attained to it from the passions and thus
conferred on him independence and felicity. Man could, of himself,
reach a complete beatitude which was not impaired by the limits
placed to his duration. The sage, a blissful being, was a god on
earth: heaven could give him nothing more. Therefore for these
philosophers the answer to the question, “What becomes of us after
death?” did not depend on moral considerations as it generally does
for us. For them it rather followed on physical
theories.If these theories allow of different solutions of the problem
of immortality, they agree on one point—the impossibility that the
soul, if it is to last longer than we, should go down into the
depths of the earth; for the soul was, as we have said, conceived
as an ardent breath; that is to say, as formed of the two elements,
air and fire, which have the property of rising to the heights. Its
very nature prevented its descent: “it is impossible to conceive
that it is borne downwards.”[37]Thus
all the vulgar notions as to Hades were in contradiction with Stoic
psychology, a point to which we will return in treating of the
nether world.[38]These
philosophers do indeed speak of Hades but, faithful to their
habits, while they use traditional terms they give them a new
meaning. “The descent into Hades” is for them simply the departing
from life, the transference of the soul to new surroundings. Thus
Epictetus, who uses this expression (κάθοδος εἰς Ἄιδου), clearly
states in another passage, “There is no Hades, no Acheron, no
Cocytus, no Pyriphlegethon, but all is filled with gods and
demons.”[39]These
gods and demons were, however, no more than personifications of the
forces of nature.[40]The true Stoic doctrine is, then, that souls, when they leave
the corpse, subsist in the atmosphere and especially in its highest
part which touches the circle of the moon.[41]But
after a longer or less interval of time they, like the flesh and
the bones, are decomposed and dissolve into the elements which
formed them.This thought, like Epicurean nihilism, often appears in
epitaphs, and shows how Stoic ideas had spread among the people.
Thus on a tombstone found in Moesia we read first the mournful
statement that there is neither love nor friendship among the dead
and that the corpse lies like a stone sunk into the ground. Then
the dead man adds:[42]“I was
once composed of earth, water and airy breath (πνεῦμα), but I
perished, and here I rest, having rendered all to the All. Such is
each man’s lot. What of it? There, whence my body came, did it
return, when it was dissolved.” Sometimes there is more insistence
on the notion that this cosmic breath, in which ours is gathered
up, is the godhead who fills and rules the world. So in this
epitaph: “The holy spirit which thou didst bear has escaped from
thy body. That body remains here and is like the earth; the spirit
pursues the revolving heavens; the spirit moves all; the spirit is
nought else than God.”[43]Elsewhere we find the following brief formula, which sums up
the same idea: “The ashes have my body; the sacred air has borne
away my soul.”[44]Very
characteristic is an inscription inspired by verses of a Greek
poet, on the tomb of a Roman woman: “Here I lie dead and I am
ashes; these ashes are earth. If the earth be a goddess, I too am a
goddess and am not dead.”[45]These verses express the same great thought in various forms:
death is disappearance into the depths of divine nature. It is not
for the preservation of an ephemeral personality that we must hope.
Our soul, a fleeting energy detached from the All, must enter again
into the All as must our body: both are absorbed by
God,
“ When that which drew from out the boundless
deepTurns again home.”[46]The fiery breath of our intelligence is gathered, as are the
matter and the humours of our organism, into the inexhaustible
reservoir which produced them, as one day the earth and the heavens
will be gathered thither also. All must be engulfed in one whole,
must lose itself in one forgetfulness. When man has reached the
term of his fate, he faints into the one power which forms and
leads the universe, just as the tired stars will be extinguished in
it, when their days shall be accomplished. Resistance to the
supreme law is vain and painful; rebellion against the irresistible
order of things is impious. The great virtue taught by Stoicism is
that of submission to the fatality which guides the world, of
joyous acceptance of the inevitable. Philosophic literature and the
epitaphs present to us, repeatedly and in a thousand forms, the
idea that we cannot strive against omnipotent necessity, that the
rule of this rigid master must be borne without tears or
recriminations. The wise man, who destroys within himself desire of
any happenings, enjoys even during this existence divine calm in
the midst of tribulations, but those whom the vicissitudes of life
drive or attract, who let illusions seduce or grieve them, will at
last obtain remission of their troubles when they reach the
tranquil haven of death. This thought is expressed by a distich
which often recurs on tombs, in Greek and in Latin. “I have fled,
escaped. Farewell, Hope and Fortune. I have nothing more to do with
you. Make others your sport.”[47]Stoic determinism found support in the astrology which
originated in Babylonia and was transplanted to Egypt, and which
spread in the Graeco-Latin world from the second century B. C.
onwards, propagating its mechanical and fatalistic conception of
the universe. According to this pseudo-science, all physical
phenomena depended absolutely, like the character and acts of men,
on the revolutions of the celestial bodies. Thus all the forces of
nature and the very energy of intelligence acted in accordance with
an inflexible necessity. Hence worship had no object and prayer no
effect. In this way the sidereal divination, which had grown up in
the temples of the East, ended in Greece, among certain of its
adepts, in a negation of the very basis of religion.[48]It is noteworthy that in the writings left to us there is
hardly an allusion to the immortality of the soul. When they speak
of what comes after death there is question only of funerals and
posthumous glory. We never find in them a promise to the
unfortunate, weighed down by misadventure and infirmities, of
consolation or compensation in the Beyond. The systematic astrology
of the Greeks limits its horizon to this world, although traces of
the belief in Hades subsist in its vocabulary and its predictions
and although this same astral divination inspired in the mysteries
certain eschatological theories, as we shall see later.[49]The rationalistic and scientific period of Hellenic thought
which began, as we have said, with Aristotle, filled the
Hellenistic period and continued until the century of Augustus.
Towards the end of the Roman Republic faith in the future life was
reduced to a minimum and the scepticism or indifference of the
Alexandrians was carried into Italy. The mocking verses of an
epigram of Callimachus, a man of learning as well as a poet, is
well known.[50]“Charidas, what is there down below? Deep darkness. But what
of the journeys upwards? All lies. And Pluto? A fable. Then we are
lost.” Catullus was to say as much, less lightly, with a deeper
feeling. “Suns can set and rise again, but we, when our brief light
is extinguished, must sleep for an eternal night.”[51]The
religions belief in retribution in the Beyond was shaken, as all
the others were, not only in literary and philosophic circles but
among a large section of the population. The old tales of the
Elysian Fields and Tartarus no longer found credence, as convincing
testimony will show us.[52]Those
who sought to preserve them could do so only by using a daring
symbol which altered their character. But the idea of conscious
survival after death was itself no longer looked upon as sure. Many
who did not go so far as to deny it brutally were firmly agnostic.
When we turn over the pages of the thick volumes of theCorpus inscriptionum, we are struck by
the small number of the epitaphs which express the hope of
immortality. The impression received is quite the contrary of that
given by going through our own graveyards or surveying the
collections of Christian epitaphs of antiquity. On by far the
larger number of the tombs the survival of the soul was neither
affirmed nor denied; it was not mentioned otherwise than by the
banal formulaDis Manibus—so
bereft of meaning that even some Christians made use of it. Or else
the authors of funereal inscriptions, like the contemporary
writers, used careful phrases which showed their mental
hesitations: “If the Manes still perceive anything.... If any
feeling subsist after death.... If there be reward for the
righteous beneath the ground.”[53]Such
doubting propositions are most frequent. The same indecision made
people return to an alternative presented by Plato in theApology,[54]before
his ideas had evolved, and repeat that death is “an end or a
passage,”—mors aut finis aut
transitus,—and no choice is made between the two
possibilities: the question is left open. The future life was
generally regarded as a consoling metaphysical conception, a mere
hypothesis supported by some thinkers, a religious hope but not an
article of faith. The lofty conclusion which ends Agricola’s eulogy
will be remembered. “If,” says Tacitus, “there be an abode of the
spirits of virtuous men, if, as sages have taught, great souls be
not extinguished with the body, rest in peace.” But side by side
with the supposition thus hazarded, the historian expresses the
assurance that Agricola will receive another reward for his merits.
All that his contemporaries have loved and admired in his character
will cause the fame of his deeds to live in men’s memory through
the eternity of ages.We here see how the perplexity in which men struggled, when
they thought of psychic survival, gave earthly immortality a
greater value in the eyes of the ancients. It was for many of them
the essential point because it alone was certain. Not to fall into
the abyss of forgetfulness seemed a sufficient reward for virtue.
“Death is to be feared by those for whom everything is extinguished
with their life, not by those whose renown cannot perish.”[55]That the commemoration of our merits may not cease when the
short time of our passage here below has ended, but may be
prolonged for as long as the sequence of future generations
lasts—this is the deep desire which stimulates virtue and excites
to effort. Cicero, when celebrating in thePro
Archia[56]the
benefits wrought by the love of glory,—from which he was by no
means exempt himself,—remarks shrewdly that even philosophers, who
claim to show its vanity, are careful to place their names at the
beginning of their books, thus showing the worth they attach to
that which they exhort others to despise. Even more than today, the
hope of a durable renown, the anxiety that their fellows should be
busy about them even after their departure, the preoccupation lest
their life should not be favourably judged by public opinion,
haunted many men, secretly or avowedly dominated their thought and
directed their actions. Even those who had played only a modest
part in the world and had made themselves known only to a narrow
circle, sought to render their memory unforgettable by building
strong tombs for themselves along the great roads. Epitaphs often
begin with the formulaMemoriae
aeternae, “To the eternal memory,” which we have
inherited, although the idea it represents no longer has for most
of us any but a very relative value.In antiquity it was first connected with the old belief in a
communion of sentiments and an exchange of services between the
deceased and their descendants who celebrated the funeral cult.
When the firm belief in the power of the shades to feel and act
ceased to exist, offerings were made with another intention:
survivors liked to think that he who had gone had not entirely
perished as long as his remembrance subsisted in the hearts of
those who had cherished him and the minds of those who had learnt
his praises. In some way, he rose from the grave in the image made
of him by the successors of those who had known him. Epicurus
himself stipulated in his will that the day of his birth should be
commemorated every month,[57]