Utilitarianism
UtilitarianismCHAPTER I. GENERAL REMARKS.CHAPTER II. WHAT UTILITARIANISM IS.CHAPTER III. OF THE ULTIMATE SANCTION OF THE PRINCIPLE OF UTILITY.CHAPTER IV. OF WHAT SORT OF PROOF THE PRINCIPLE OF UTILITY IS SUSCEPTIBLE.CHAPTER V. ON THE CONNEXION BETWEEN JUSTICE AND UTILITY.Copyright
Utilitarianism
John Stuart Mill
CHAPTER I. GENERAL REMARKS.
There are few circumstances among those which make up the present
condition of human knowledge, more unlike what might have been
expected, or more significant of the backward state in which
speculation on the most important subjects still lingers, than the
little progress which has been made in the decision of the
controversy respecting the criterion of right and wrong. From the
dawn of philosophy, the question concerning the summum bonum, or,
what is the same thing, concerning the foundation of morality, has
been accounted the main problem in speculative thought, has
occupied the most gifted intellects, and divided them into sects
and schools, carrying on a vigorous warfare against one another.
And after more than two thousand years the same discussions
continue, philosophers are still ranged under the same contending
banners, and neither thinkers nor mankind at large seem nearer to
being unanimous on the subject, than when the youth Socrates
listened to the old Protagoras, and asserted (if Plato's dialogue
be grounded on a real conversation) the theory of utilitarianism
against the popular morality of the so-called sophist.
It is true that similar confusion and uncertainty, and in some
cases similar discordance, exist respecting the first principles of
all the sciences, not excepting that which is deemed the most
certain of them, mathematics; without much impairing, generally
indeed without impairing at all, the trustworthiness of the
conclusions of those sciences. An apparent anomaly, the explanation
of which is, that the detailed doctrines of a science are not
usually deduced from, nor depend for their evidence upon, what are
called its first principles. Were it not so, there would be no
science more precarious, or whose conclusions were more
insufficiently made out, than algebra; which derives none of its
certainty from what are commonly taught to learners as its
elements, since these, as laid down by some of its most eminent
teachers, are as full of fictions as English law, and of mysteries
as theology. The truths which are ultimately accepted as the first
principles of a science, are really the last results of
metaphysical analysis, practised on the elementary notions with
which the science is conversant; and their relation to the science
is not that of foundations to an edifice, but of roots to a tree,
which may perform their office equally well though they be never
dug down to and exposed to light. But though in science the
particular truths precede the general theory, the contrary might be
expected to be the case with a practical art, such as morals or
legislation. All action is for the sake of some end, and rules of
action, it seems natural to suppose, must take their whole
character and colour from the end to which they are subservient.
When we engage in a pursuit, a clear and precise conception of what
we are pursuing would seem to be the first thing we need, instead
of the last we are to look forward to. A test of right and wrong
must be the means, one would think, of ascertaining what is right
or wrong, and not a consequence of having already ascertained
it.
The difficulty is not avoided by having recourse to the popular
theory of a natural faculty, a sense or instinct, informing us of
right and wrong. For—besides that the existence of such a moral
instinct is itself one of the matters in dispute—those believers in
it who have any pretensions to philosophy, have been obliged to
abandon the idea that it discerns what is right or wrong in the
particular case in hand, as our other senses discern the sight or
sound actually present. Our moral faculty, according to all those
of its interpreters who are entitled to the name of thinkers,
supplies us only with the general principles of moral judgments; it
is a branch of our reason, not of our sensitive faculty; and must
be looked to for the abstract doctrines of morality, not for
perception of it in the concrete. The intuitive, no less than what
may be termed the inductive, school of ethics, insists on the
necessity of general laws. They both agree that the morality of an
individual action is not a question of direct perception, but of
the application of a law to an individual case. They recognise
also, to a great extent, the same moral laws; but differ as to
their evidence, and the source from which they derive their
authority. According to the one opinion, the principles of morals
are evident à priori, requiring nothing to command assent, except
that the meaning of the terms be understood. According to the other
doctrine, right and wrong, as well as truth and falsehood, are
questions of observation and experience. But both hold equally that
morality must be deduced from principles; and the intuitive school
affirm as strongly as the inductive, that there is a science of
morals. Yet they seldom attempt to make out a list of the à priori
principles which are to serve as the premises of the science; still
more rarely do they make any effort to reduce those various
principles to one first principle, or common ground of obligation.
They either assume the ordinary precepts of morals as of à priori
authority, or they lay down as the common groundwork of those
maxims, some generality much less obviously authoritative than the
maxims themselves, and which has never succeeded in gaining popular
acceptance. Yet to support their pretensions there ought either to
be some one fundamental principle or law, at the root of all
morality, or if there be several, there should be a determinate
order of precedence among them; and the one principle, or the rule
for deciding between the various principles when they conflict,
ought to be self-evident.
To inquire how far the bad effects of this deficiency have been
mitigated in practice, or to what extent the moral beliefs of
mankind have been vitiated or made uncertain by the absence of any
distinct recognition of an ultimate standard, would imply a
complete survey and criticism of past and present ethical doctrine.
It would, however, be easy to show that whatever steadiness or
consistency these moral beliefs have attained, has been mainly due
to the tacit influence of a standard not recognised. Although the
non-existence of an acknowledged first principle has made ethics
not so much a guide as a consecration of men's actual sentiments,
still, as men's sentiments, both of favour and of aversion, are
greatly influenced by what they suppose to be the effects of things
upon their happiness, the principle of utility, or as Bentham
latterly called it, the greatest happiness principle, has had a
large share in forming the moral doctrines even of those who most
scornfully reject its authority. Nor is there any school of thought
which refuses to admit that the influence of actions on happiness
is a most material and even predominant consideration in many of
the details of morals, however unwilling to acknowledge it as the
fundamental principle of morality, and the source of moral
obligation. I might go much further, and say that to all those à
priori moralists who deem it necessary to argue at all, utilitarian
arguments are indispensable. It is not my present purpose to
criticise these thinkers; but I cannot help referring, for
illustration, to a systematic treatise by one of the most
illustrious of them, the Metaphysics of Ethics, by Kant. This
remarkable man, whose system of thought will long remain one of the
landmarks in the history of philosophical speculation, does, in the
treatise in question, lay down an universal first principle as the
origin and ground of moral obligation; it is this:—'So act, that
the rule on which thou actest would admit of being adopted as a law
by all rational beings.' But when he begins to deduce from this
precept any of the actual duties of morality, he fails, almost
grotesquely, to show that there would be any contradiction, any
logical (not to say physical) impossibility, in the adoption by all
rational beings of the most outrageously immoral rules of conduct.
All he shows is that the consequences of their universal adoption
would be such as no one would choose to incur.
On the present occasion, I shall, without further discussion of the
other theories, attempt to contribute something towards the
understanding and appreciation of the Utilitarian or Happiness
theory, and towards such proof as it is susceptible of. It is
evident that this cannot be proof in the ordinary and popular
meaning of the term. Questions of ultimate ends are not amenable to
direct proof. Whatever can be proved to be good, must be so by
being shown to be a means to something admitted to be good without
proof. The medical art is proved to be good, by its conducing to
health; but how is it possible to prove that health is good? The
art of music is good, for the reason, among others, that it
produces pleasure; but what proof is it possible to give that
pleasure is good? If, then, it is asserted that there is a
comprehensive formula, including all things which are in themselves
good, and that whatever else is good, is not so as an end, but as a
mean, the formula may be accepted or rejected, but is not a subject
of what is commonly understood by proof. We are not, however, to
infer that its acceptance or rejection must depend on blind
impulse, or arbitrary choice. There is a larger meaning of the word
proof, in which this question is as amenable to it as any other of
the disputed questions of philosophy. The subject is within the
cognizance of the rational faculty; and neither does that faculty
deal with it solely in the way of intuition. Considerations may be
presented capable of determining the intellect either to give or
withhold its assent to the doctrine; and this is equivalent to
proof.
We shall examine presently of what nature are these considerations;
in what manner they apply to the case, and what rational grounds,
therefore, can be given for accepting or rejecting the utilitarian
formula. But it is a preliminary condition of rational acceptance
or rejection, that the formula should be correctly understood. I
believe that the very imperfect notion ordinarily formed of its
meaning, is the chief obstacle which impedes its reception; and
that could it be cleared, even from only the grosser
misconceptions, the question would be greatly simplified, and a
large proportion of its difficulties removed. Before, therefore, I
attempt to enter into the philosophical grounds which can be given
for assenting to the utilitarian standard, I shall offer some
illustrations of the doctrine itself; with the view of showing more
clearly what it is, distinguishing it from what it is not, and
disposing of such of the practical objections to it as either
originate in, or are closely connected with, mistaken
interpretations of its meaning. Having thus prepared the ground, I
shall afterwards endeavour to throw such light as I can upon the
question, considered as one of philosophical theory.
CHAPTER II. WHAT UTILITARIANISM IS.
A passing remark is all that needs be given to the ignorant blunder
of supposing that those who stand up for utility as the test of
right and wrong, use the term in that restricted and merely
colloquial sense in which utility is opposed to pleasure. An
apology is due to the philosophical opponents of utilitarianism,
for even the momentary appearance of confounding them with any one
capable of so absurd a misconception; which is the more
extraordinary, inasmuch as the contrary accusation, of referring
everything to pleasure, and that too in its grossest form, is
another of the common charges against utilitarianism: and, as has
been pointedly remarked by an able writer, the same sort of
persons, and often the very same persons, denounce the theory "as
impracticably dry when the word utility precedes the word pleasure,
and as too practicably voluptuous when the word pleasure precedes
the word utility." Those who know anything about the matter are
aware that every writer, from Epicurus to Bentham, who maintained
the theory of utility, meant by it, not something to be
contradistinguished from pleasure, but pleasure itself, together
with exemption from pain; and instead of opposing the useful to the
agreeable or the ornamental, have always declared that the useful
means these, among other things. Yet the common herd, including the
herd of writers, not only in newspapers and periodicals, but in
books of weight and pretension, are perpetually falling into this
shallow mistake. Having caught up the word utilitarian, while
knowing nothing whatever about it but its sound, they habitually
express by it the rejection, or the neglect, of pleasure in some of
its forms; of beauty, of ornament, or of amusement. Nor is the term
thus ignorantly misapplied solely in disparagement, but
occasionally in compliment; as though it implied superiority to
frivolity and the mere pleasures of the moment. And this perverted
use is the only one in which the word is popularly known, and the
one from which the new generation are acquiring their sole notion
of its meaning. Those who introduced the word, but who had for many
years discontinued it as a distinctive appellation, may well feel
themselves called upon to resume it, if by doing so they can hope
to contribute anything towards rescuing it from this utter
degradation.[A]
The creed which accepts as the foundation of morals, Utility, or
the Greatest Happiness Principle, holds that actions are right in
proportion as they tend to promote happiness, wrong as they tend to
produce the reverse of happiness. By happiness is intended
pleasure, and the absence of pain; by unhappiness, pain, and the
privation of pleasure. To give a clear view of the moral standard
set up by the theory, much more requires to be said; in particular,
what things it includes in the ideas of pain and pleasure; and to
what extent this is left an open question. But these supplementary
explanations do not affect the theory of life on which this theory
of morality is grounded—namely, that pleasure, and freedom from
pain, are the only things desirable as ends; and that all desirable
things (which are as numerous in the utilitarian as in any other
scheme) are desirable either for the pleasure inherent in
themselves, or as means to the promotion of pleasure and the
prevention of pain.
Now, such a theory of life excites in many minds, and among them in
some of the most estimable in feeling and purpose, inveterate
dislike. To suppose that life has (as they express it) no higher
end than pleasure—no better and nobler object of desire and
pursuit—they designate as utterly mean and grovelling; as a
doctrine worthy only of swine, to whom the followers of Epicurus
were, at a very early period, contemptuously likened; and modern
holders of the doctrine are occasionally made the subject of
equally polite comparisons by its German, French, and English
assailants.