SECTION I. OF THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF MORALS.
SECTION II. OF BENEVOLENCE.
SECTION III. OF JUSTICE.
SECTION IV.
SECTION V. WHY UTILITY PLEASES.
SECTION VI. OF QUALITIES USEFUL TO OURSELVES.
SECTION VII.
SECTION VIII.
SECTION IX. CONCLUSION.
APPENDIX I. CONCERNING MORAL SENTIMENT
APPENDIX II. OF SELF-LOVE.
APPENDIX III. SOME FARTHER CONSIDERATIONS WITH REGARD TO JUSTICE.
APPENDIX IV. OF SOME VERBAL DISPUTES.
SECTION I. OF THE GENERAL PRINCIPLES OF MORALS.
DISPUTES
with men, pertinaciously obstinate in their principles, are, of all
others, the most irksome; except, perhaps, those with persons,
entirely disingenuous, who really do not believe the opinions they
defend, but engage in the controversy, from affectation, from a
spirit of opposition, or from a desire of showing wit and ingenuity,
superior to the rest of mankind. The same blind adherence to their
own arguments is to be expected in both; the same contempt of their
antagonists; and the same passionate vehemence, in inforcing
sophistry and falsehood. And as reasoning is not the source, whence
either disputant derives his tenets; it is in vain to expect, that
any logic, which speaks not to the affections, will ever engage him
to embrace sounder principles.Those
who have denied the reality of moral distinctions, may be ranked
among the disingenuous disputants; nor is it conceivable, that any
human creature could ever seriously believe, that all characters and
actions were alike entitled to the affection and regard of everyone.
The difference, which nature has placed between one man and another,
is so wide, and this difference is still so much farther widened, by
education, example, and habit, that, where the opposite extremes come
at once under our apprehension, there is no scepticism so scrupulous,
and scarce any assurance so determined, as absolutely to deny all
distinction between them. Let a man's insensibility be ever so great,
he must often be touched with the images of Right and Wrong; and let
his prejudices be ever so obstinate, he must observe, that others are
susceptible of like impressions. The only way, therefore, of
converting an antagonist of this kind, is to leave him to himself.
For, finding that nobody keeps up the controversy with him, it is
probable he will, at last, of himself, from mere weariness, come over
to the side of common sense and reason.There
has been a controversy started of late, much better worth
examination, concerning the general foundation of Morals; whether
they be derived from Reason, or from Sentiment; whether we attain the
knowledge of them by a chain of argument and induction, or by an
immediate feeling and finer internal sense; whether, like all sound
judgement of truth and falsehood, they should be the same to every
rational intelligent being; or whether, like the perception of beauty
and deformity, they be founded entirely on the particular fabric and
constitution of the human species.The
ancient philosophers, though they often affirm, that virtue is
nothing but conformity to reason, yet, in general, seem to consider
morals as deriving their existence from taste and sentiment. On the
other hand, our modern enquirers, though they also talk much of the
beauty of virtue, and deformity of vice, yet have commonly
endeavoured to account for these distinctions by metaphysical
reasonings, and by deductions from the most abstract principles of
the understanding. Such confusion reigned in these subjects, that an
opposition of the greatest consequence could prevail between one
system and another, and even in the parts of almost each individual
system; and yet nobody, till very lately, was ever sensible of it.
The elegant Lord Shaftesbury, who first gave occasion to remark this
distinction, and who, in general, adhered to the principles of the
ancients, is not, himself, entirely free from the same confusion.It
must be acknowledged, that both sides of the question are susceptible
of specious arguments. Moral distinctions, it may be said, are
discernible by pure reason: else, whence the many disputes that reign
in common life, as well as in philosophy, with regard to this
subject: the long chain of proofs often produced on both sides; the
examples cited, the authorities appealed to, the analogies employed,
the fallacies detected, the inferences drawn, and the several
conclusions adjusted to their proper principles. Truth is disputable;
not taste: what exists in the nature of things is the standard of our
judgement; what each man feels within himself is the standard of
sentiment. Propositions in geometry may be proved, systems in physics
may be controverted; but the harmony of verse, the tenderness of
passion, the brilliancy of wit, must give immediate pleasure. No man
reasons concerning another's beauty; but frequently concerning the
justice or injustice of his actions. In every criminal trial the
first object of the prisoner is to disprove the facts alleged, and
deny the actions imputed to him: the second to prove, that, even if
these actions were real, they might be justified, as innocent and
lawful. It is confessedly by deductions of the understanding, that
the first point is ascertained: how can we suppose that a different
faculty of the mind is employed in fixing the other? On the other
hand, those who would resolve all moral determinations into
sentiment, may endeavour to show, that it is impossible for reason
ever to draw conclusions of this nature. To virtue, say they, it
belongs to be amiable, and vice odious. This forms their very nature
or essence. But can reason or argumentation distribute these
different epithets to any subjects, and pronounce beforehand, that
this must produce love, and that hatred? Or what other reason can we
ever assign for these affections, but the original fabric and
formation of the human mind, which is naturally adapted to receive
them?The
end of all moral speculations is to teach us our duty; and, by proper
representations of the deformity of vice and beauty of virtue, beget
correspondent habits, and engage us to avoid the one, and embrace the
other. But is this ever to be expected from inferences and
conclusions of the understanding, which of themselves have no hold of
the affections or set in motion the active powers of men? They
discover truths: but where the truths which they discover are
indifferent, and beget no desire or aversion, they can have no
influence on conduct and behaviour. What is honourable, what is fair,
what is becoming, what is noble, what is generous, takes possession
of the heart, and animates us to embrace and maintain it. What is
intelligible, what is evident, what is probable, what is true,
procures only the cool assent of the understanding; and gratifying a
speculative curiosity, puts an end to our researches.Extinguish
all the warm feelings and prepossessions in favour of virtue, and all
disgust or aversion to vice: render men totally indifferent towards
these distinctions; and morality is no longer a practical study, nor
has any tendency to regulate our lives and actions.These
arguments on each side (and many more might be produced) are so
plausible, that I am apt to suspect, they may, the one as well as the
other, be solid and satisfactory, and that reason and sentiment
concur in almost all moral determinations and conclusions. The final
sentence, it is probable, which pronounces characters and actions
amiable or odious, praise-worthy or blameable; that which stamps on
them the mark of honour or infamy, approbation or censure; that which
renders morality an active principle and constitutes virtue our
happiness, and vice our misery; it is probable, I say, that this
final sentence depends on some internal sense or feeling, which
nature has made universal in the whole species. For what else can
have an influence of this nature? But in order to pave the way for
such a sentiment, and give a proper discernment of its object, it is
often necessary, we find, that much reasoning should precede, that
nice distinctions be made, just conclusions drawn, distant
comparisons formed, complicated relations examined, and general facts
fixed and ascertained. Some species of beauty, especially the natural
kinds, on their first appearance, command our affection and
approbation; and where they fail of this effect, it is impossible for
any reasoning to redress their influence, or adapt them better to our
taste and sentiment. But in many orders of beauty, particularly those
of the finer arts, it is requisite to employ much reasoning, in order
to feel the proper sentiment; and a false relish may frequently be
corrected by argument and reflection. There are just grounds to
conclude, that moral beauty partakes much of this latter species, and
demands the assistance of our intellectual faculties, in order to
give it a suitable influence on the human mind.But
though this question, concerning the general principles of morals, be
curious and important, it is needless for us, at present, to employ
farther care in our researches concerning it. For if we can be so
happy, in the course of this enquiry, as to discover the true origin
of morals, it will then easily appear how far either sentiment or
reason enters into all determinations of this nature [Footnote: See
Appendix I]. In order to attain this purpose, we shall endeavour to
follow a very simple method: we shall analyse that complication of
mental qualities, which form what, in common life, we call Personal
Merit: we shall consider every attribute of the mind, which renders a
man an object either of esteem and affection, or of hatred and
contempt; every habit or sentiment or faculty, which, if ascribed to
any person, implies either praise or blame, and may enter into any
panegyric or satire of his character and manners. The quick
sensibility, which, on this head, is so universal among mankind,
gives a philosopher sufficient assurance, that he can never be
considerably mistaken in framing the catalogue, or incur any danger
of misplacing the objects of his contemplation: he needs only enter
into his own breast for a moment, and consider whether or not he
should desire to have this or that quality ascribed to him, and
whether such or such an imputation would proceed from a friend or an
enemy. The very nature of language guides us almost infallibly in
forming a judgement of this nature; and as every tongue possesses one
set of words which are taken in a good sense, and another in the
opposite, the least acquaintance with the idiom suffices, without any
reasoning, to direct us in collecting and arranging the estimable or
blameable qualities of men. The only object of reasoning is to
discover the circumstances on both sides, which are common to these
qualities; to observe that particular in which the estimable
qualities agree on the one hand, and the blameable on the other; and
thence to reach the foundation of ethics, and find those universal
principles, from which all censure or approbation is ultimately
derived. As this is a question of fact, not of abstract science, we
can only expect success, by following the experimental method, and
deducing general maxims from a comparison of particular instances.
The other scientific method, where a general abstract principle is
first established, and is afterwards branched out into a variety of
inferences and conclusions, may be more perfect in itself, but suits
less the imperfection of human nature, and is a common source of
illusion and mistake in this as well as in other subjects. Men are
now cured of their passion for hypotheses and systems in natural
philosophy, and will hearken to no arguments but those which are
derived from experience. It is full time they should attempt a like
reformation in all moral disquisitions; and reject every system of
ethics, however subtle or ingenious, which is not founded on fact and
observation.We
shall begin our enquiry on this head by the consideration of the
social virtues, Benevolence and Justice. The explication of them will
probably give us an opening by which the others may be accounted for.