INTRODUCTION.
THE TRUE OR ANTHROPOLOGICAL ESSENCE OF RELIGION.
GOD AS A BEING OF THE UNDERSTANDING.
GOD AS A MORAL BEING, OR LAW.
THE MYSTERY OF THE INCARNATION; OR, GOD AS LOVE, AS A BEING OF THE HEART.
THE MYSTERY OF THE SUFFERING GOD.
THE MYSTERY OF THE TRINITY AND THE MOTHER OF GOD.
THE MYSTERY OF THE LOGOS AND DIVINE IMAGE.
THE MYSTERY OF THE COSMOGONICAL PRINCIPLE IN GOD.
THE MYSTERY OF MYSTICISM, OR OF NATURE IN GOD.
THE MYSTERY OF PROVIDENCE, AND CREATION OUT OF NOTHING.
THE SIGNIFICANCE OF THE CREATION IN JUDAISM.
THE OMNIPOTENCE OF FEELING, OR THE MYSTERY OF PRAYER.
THE MYSTERY OF FAITH—THE MYSTERY OF MIRACLE.
THE MYSTERY OF THE RESURRECTION AND OF THE MIRACULOUS CONCEPTION.
THE MYSTERY OF THE CHRISTIAN CHRIST, OR THE PERSONAL GOD.
THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN CHRISTIANITY AND HEATHENISM.
THE CHRISTIAN SIGNIFICANCE OF VOLUNTARY CELIBACY AND MONACHISM.
THE CHRISTIAN HEAVEN, OR PERSONAL IMMORTALITY.
THE FALSE OR THEOLOGICAL ESSENCE OF RELIGION.
THE ESSENTIAL STANDPOINT OF RELIGION.
THE CONTRADICTION IN THE EXISTENCE OF GOD.
THE CONTRADICTION IN THE REVELATION OF GOD.
THE CONTRADICTION IN THE NATURE OF GOD IN GENERAL.
THE CONTRADICTION IN THE SPECULATIVE DOCTRINE OF GOD.
THE CONTRADICTION IN THE TRINITY.
THE CONTRADICTION IN THE SACRAMENTS.
THE CONTRADICTION OF FAITH AND LOVE.
CONCLUDING APPLICATION.
EXPLANATIONS—REMARKS—ILLUSTRATIVE CITATIONS.
PREFACE TO THE SECOND EDITION.1
The
clamour excited by the present work has not surprised me, and hence
it has not in the least moved me from my position. On the contrary,
I
have once more, in all calmness, subjected my work to the severest
scrutiny, both historical and philosophical; I have, as far as
possible, freed it from its defects of form, and enriched it with
new
developments, illustrations, and historical
testimonies,—testimonies
in the highest degree striking and irrefragable. Now that I have
thus
verified my analysis by historical proofs, it is to be hoped that
readers whose eyes are not sealed will be convinced and will admit,
even though reluctantly, that my work contains a faithful, correct
translation of the Christian religion out of the Oriental language
of
imagery into plain speech. And it has no pretension to be anything
more than a close translation, or, to speak literally, an empirical
or historico-philosophical analysis, a solution of the enigma of
the
Christian religion. The general propositions which I premise in the
Introduction are no
à priori,
excogitated propositions, no products of speculation; they have
arisen out of the analysis of religion; they are only, as indeed
are
all the fundamental ideas of the work, generalisations from the
known
manifestations of human nature, and in particular of the religious
consciousness,—facts converted into thoughts,
i.e.,
expressed in general terms, and thus made the property of the
understanding. The ideas of my work are only conclusions,
consequences,
drawn from premisses which are not themselves mere ideas, but
objective facts either actual or historical—facts which had not
their place in my head simply in virtue of their ponderous
existence
in folio. I unconditionally repudiate
absolute,
immaterial, self-sufficing speculation—that speculation which draws
its material from within. I differ
toto cœlo
from those philosophers who pluck out their eyes that they may see
better; for
my
thought I require the senses, especially sight; I found my ideas on
materials which can be appropriated only through the activity of
the
senses. I do not generate the object from the thought, but the
thought from the object; and I hold
that
alone to be an object which has an existence beyond one’s own
brain. I am an idealist only in the region of
practical
philosophy, that is, I do not regard the limits of the past and
present as the limits of humanity, of the future; on the contrary,
I
firmly believe that many things—yes, many things—which with the
short-sighted, pusillanimous practical men of to-day, pass for
flights of imagination, for ideas never to be realised, for mere
chimeras, will to-morrow,
i.e.,
in the next century,—centuries in individual life are days in the
life of humanity,—exist in full reality. Briefly, the “Idea” is
to me only faith in the historical future, in the triumph of truth
and virtue; it has for me only a political and moral significance;
for in the sphere of strictly theoretical philosophy, I attach
myself, in direct opposition to the Hegelian philosophy, only
to
realism,
to materialism in the sense above indicated. The maxim hitherto
adopted by speculative philosophy: All that is mine I carry with
me,
the old
omnia mea mecum porto,
I cannot, alas! appropriate. I have many things outside myself,
which
I cannot convey either in my pocket or my head, but which
nevertheless I look upon as belonging to me, not indeed as a mere
man—a view not now in question—but as a philosopher. I am nothing
but a
natural philosopher in the domain of mind;
and the natural philosopher can do nothing without instruments,
without material means. In this character I have written the
present
work, which consequently contains nothing else than the principle
of
a new philosophy verified practically,
i.e.,
in concreto,
in application to a special object, but an object which has a
universal significance: namely, to religion, in which this
principle
is exhibited, developed, and thoroughly carried out. This
philosophy
is essentially distinguished from the systems hitherto prevalent,
in
that it corresponds to the real, complete nature of man; but for
that
very reason it is antagonistic to minds perverted and crippled by a
superhuman,
i.e.,
anti-human, anti-natural religion and speculation. It does not, as
I
have already said elsewhere, regard the
pen
as the only fit organ for the revelation of truth, but the eye and
ear, the hand and foot; it does not identify the
idea
of the fact with the fact itself, so as to reduce real existence to
an existence on paper, but it separates the two, and precisely by
this separation attains to the
fact itself;
it recognises as the true thing, not the thing as it is an object
of
the abstract reason, but as it is an object of the real, complete
man, and hence as it is itself a real, complete thing. This
philosophy does not rest on an Understanding
per se,
on an absolute, nameless understanding, belonging one knows not to
whom, but on the understanding of man;—though not, I grant, on that
of man enervated by speculation and dogma;—and it speaks the
language of men, not an empty, unknown tongue. Yes, both in
substance
and in speech, it places philosophy in
the negation of philosophy,
i.e.,
it declares
that
alone to be the true philosophy which is converted
in succum et sanguinem,
which is incarnate in Man; and hence it finds its highest triumph
in
the fact that to all dull and pedantic minds, which place
the
essence
of philosophy in the
show
of philosophy, it appears to be no philosophy at all.This
philosophy has for its principle, not the Substance of Spinoza, not
the
ego
of Kant and Fichte, not the Absolute Identity of Schelling, not the
Absolute Mind of Hegel, in short, no abstract, merely conceptional
being, but a
real
being, the true
Ens realissimum—man;
its principle, therefore, is in the highest degree positive and
real.
It generates thought from the
opposite
of thought, from Matter, from existence, from the senses; it has
relation to its object first through the senses,
i.e.,
passively, before defining it in thought. Hence my work, as a
specimen of this philosophy, so far from being a production to be
placed in the category of Speculation,—although in another point of
view it is the true, the incarnate result of prior philosophical
systems,—is the direct opposite of speculation, nay, puts an end to
it by explaining it. Speculation makes religion say only what it
has
itself
thought, and expressed far better than religion; it assigns a
meaning
to religion without any reference to the
actual
meaning of religion; it does not look beyond itself. I, on the
contrary, let religion itself speak; I constitute myself only its
listener and interpreter, not its prompter. Not to invent, but to
discover, “to unveil existence,” has been my sole object; to
see
correctly, my sole endeavour. It is not I, but religion that
worships
man, although religion, or rather theology, denies this; it is not
I,
an insignificant individual, but religion itself that says: God is
man, man is God; it is not I, but religion that denies the God who
is
not
man, but only an
ens rationis,—since
it makes God become man, and then constitutes this God, not
distinguished from man, having a human form, human feelings, and
human thoughts, the object of its worship and veneration. I have
only
found the key to the cipher of the Christian religion, only
extricated its true meaning from the web of contradictions and
delusions called theology;—but in doing so I have certainly
committed a sacrilege. If therefore my work is negative,
irreligious,
atheistic, let it be remembered that atheism—at least in the sense
of this work—is the secret of religion itself; that religion
itself, not indeed on the surface, but fundamentally, not in
intention or according to its own supposition, but in its heart, in
its essence, believes in nothing else than the truth and divinity
of
human nature. Or let it be
proved
that the historical as well as the rational arguments of my work
are
false; let them be refuted—not, however, I entreat, by judicial
denunciations, or theological jeremiads, by the trite phrases of
speculation, or other pitiful expedients for which I have no name,
but by
reasons,
and such reasons as I have not already thoroughly answered.Certainly,
my work is negative, destructive; but, be it observed, only in
relation to the
unhuman,
not to the human elements of religion. It is therefore divided into
two parts, of which the first is, as to its main idea,
positive,
the second, including the Appendix, not wholly, but in the
main,
negative;
in both, however, the same positions are proved, only in a
different
or rather opposite manner. The first exhibits religion in
its
essence,
its
truth,
the second exhibits it in its
contradictions;
the first is development, the second polemic; thus the one is,
according to the nature of the case, calmer, the other more
vehement.
Development advances gently, contest impetuously; for development
is
self-contented at every stage, contest only at the last blow.
Development is deliberate, but contest resolute. Development
is
light,
contest
fire.
Hence results a difference between the two parts even as to their
form. Thus in the first part I show that the true sense of Theology
is Anthropology, that there is no distinction between the
predicates
of the divine and human nature, and, consequently, no distinction
between the divine and human
subject:
I say
consequently,
for wherever, as is especially the case in theology, the predicates
are not accidents, but express the essence of the subject, there is
no distinction between subject and predicate, the one can be put in
the place of the other; on which point I refer the reader to the
Analytics of Aristotle, or even merely to the Introduction of
Porphyry. In the second part, on the other hand, I show that the
distinction which is made, or rather supposed to be made, between
the
theological and anthropological predicates resolves itself into an
absurdity. Here is a striking example. In the first part I prove
that
the Son of God is
in religion
a real son, the son of God in the same sense in which man is the
son
of man, and I find therein the
truth,
the
essence
of religion, that it conceives and affirms a profoundly human
relation as a divine relation; on the other hand, in the second
part
I show that the Son of God—not indeed in religion, but in theology,
which is the reflection of religion upon itself,—is not a son in
the natural, human sense, but in an entirely different manner,
contradictory to Nature and reason, and therefore absurd, and I
find
in this negation of human sense and the human understanding, the
negation of religion. Accordingly the first part is the
direct,
the second the
indirect
proof, that theology is anthropology: hence the second part
necessarily has reference to the first; it has no independent
significance; its only aim is to show that the sense in which
religion is interpreted in the previous part of the work
must
be the true one, because the contrary is absurd. In brief, in the
first part I am chiefly concerned with
religion,
in the second with
theology:
I say
chiefly,
for it was impossible to exclude theology from the first part, or
religion from the second. A mere glance will show that my
investigation includes
speculative
theology or philosophy, and not, as has been here and there
erroneously supposed,
common
theology only, a kind of trash from which I rather keep as clear as
possible, (though, for the rest, I am sufficiently well acquainted
with it), confining myself always to the most essential, strict and
necessary definition of the object,2
and hence to that definition which gives to an object the most
general interest, and raises it above the sphere of theology. But
it
is with theology that I have to do, not with theologians; for I can
only undertake to characterise what is
primary,—the
original,
not the copy,
principles,
not persons,
species,
not individuals,
objects of history,
not objects of the
chronique scandaleuse.If
my work contained only the second part, it would be perfectly just
to
accuse it of a negative tendency, to represent the proposition:
Religion is nothing, is an absurdity, as its essential purport. But
I
by no means say (that were an easy task!): God is nothing, the
Trinity is nothing, the Word of God is nothing, &c. I only show
that they are not
that
which the illusions of theology make them,—not foreign, but native
mysteries, the mysteries of human nature; I show that religion
takes
the apparent, the superficial in Nature and humanity for the
essential, and hence conceives their true essence as a separate,
special existence: that consequently, religion, in the definitions
which it gives of God,
e.g.,
of the Word of God,—at least in those definitions which are not
negative in the sense above alluded to,—only defines or makes
objective the true nature of the human word. The reproach that
according to my book religion is an absurdity, a nullity, a pure
illusion, would be well founded only if, according to it, that into
which I resolve religion, which I prove to be its true object and
substance, namely,
man,—anthropology,
were an absurdity, a nullity, a pure illusion. But so far from
giving
a trivial or even a subordinate significance to anthropology,—a
significance which is assigned to it only just so long as a
theology
stands above it and in opposition to it,—I, on the contrary, while
reducing theology to anthropology, exalt anthropology into
theology,
very much as Christianity, while lowering God into man, made man
into
God; though, it is true, this human God was by a further process
made
a transcendental, imaginary God, remote from man. Hence it is
obvious
that I do not take the word anthropology in the sense of the
Hegelian
or of any other philosophy, but in an infinitely higher and more
general sense.Religion
is the dream of the human mind. But even in dreams we do not find
ourselves in emptiness or in heaven, but on earth, in the realm of
reality; we only see real things in the entrancing splendour of
imagination and caprice, instead of in the simple daylight of
reality
and necessity. Hence I do nothing more to religion—and to
speculative philosophy and theology also—than to open its eyes, or
rather to turn its gaze from the internal towards the
external,
i.e.,
I change the object as it is in the imagination into the object as
it
is in reality.But
certainly for the present age, which prefers the sign to the thing
signified, the copy to the original, fancy to reality, the
appearance
to the essence, this change, inasmuch as it does away with
illusion,
is an absolute annihilation, or at least a reckless profanation;
for
in these days
illusion
only is
sacred, truth profane.
Nay, sacredness is held to be enhanced in proportion as truth
decreases and illusion increases, so that the highest degree of
illusion comes to be the highest degree of sacredness. Religion has
disappeared, and for it has been substituted, even among
Protestants,
the
appearance
of religion—the Church—in order at least that “the faith” may
be imparted to the ignorant and indiscriminating multitude;
that
faith being still the Christian, because the Christian churches
stand
now as they did a thousand years ago, and now, as formerly,
the
external signs
of the faith are in vogue. That which has no longer any existence
in
faith (the faith of the modern world is only an ostensible faith, a
faith which does not believe what it fancies that it believes, and
is
only an undecided, pusillanimous unbelief) is still to pass current
as
opinion:
that which is no longer sacred in itself and in truth is still at
least to
seem
sacred. Hence the simulated religious indignation of the present
age,
the age of shows and illusion, concerning my analysis, especially
of
the Sacraments. But let it not be demanded of an author who
proposes
to himself as his goal not the favour of his contemporaries, but
only
the truth, the unveiled, naked truth, that he should have or feign
respect towards an empty appearance, especially as the object which
underlies this appearance is in itself the culminating point of
religion,
i.e.,
the point at which the religious slides into the irreligious. Thus
much in justification, not in excuse, of my analysis of the
Sacraments.With
regard to the true bearing of my analysis of the Sacraments,
especially as presented in the concluding chapter, I only remark,
that I therein illustrate by a palpable and visible example the
essential purport, the peculiar theme of my work; that I therein
call
upon the senses themselves to witness to the truth of my analysis
and
my ideas, and demonstrate
ad oculos, ad tactum, ad gustum,
what I have taught
ad captum
throughout the previous pages. As, namely, the water of Baptism,
the
wine and bread of the Lord’s Supper, taken in their natural power
and significance, are and effect infinitely more than in a
supernaturalistic, illusory significance; so the object of religion
in general, conceived in the sense of this work,
i.e.,
the anthropological sense, is infinitely more productive and real,
both in theory and practice, than when accepted in the sense of
theology. For as that which is or is supposed to be imparted in the
water, bread, and wine, over and above these natural substances
themselves, is something in the imagination only, but in truth, in
reality, nothing; so also the object of religion in general, the
Divine essence, in distinction from the essence of Nature and
Humanity,—that is to say, if its attributes, as understanding,
love, &c., are and signify something else than these attributes
as they belong to man and Nature,—is only something in the
imagination, but in truth and reality nothing. Therefore—this is
the moral of the fable—we should not, as is the case in theology
and speculative philosophy, make real beings and things into
arbitrary signs, vehicles, symbols, or predicates of a distinct,
transcendent, absolute,
i.e.,
abstract being; but we should accept and understand them in the
significance which they have in themselves, which is identical with
their qualities, with those conditions which make them what they
are:—thus only do we obtain the key to a
real theory and practice.
I, in fact, put in the place of the barren baptismal water, the
beneficent effect of real water. How “watery,” how trivial! Yes,
indeed, very trivial. But so Marriage, in its time, was a
very trivial truth,
which Luther, on the ground of his natural good sense, maintained
in
opposition to the seemingly holy illusion of celibacy. But while I
thus view water as a real thing, I at the same time intend it as a
vehicle, an image, an example, a symbol, of the “unholy” spirit
of my work, just as the water of Baptism—the object of my
analysis—is at once literal and symbolical water. It is the same
with bread and wine. Malignity has hence drawn the conclusion that
bathing, eating, and drinking are the
summa summarum,
the positive result of my work. I make no other reply than this: If
the whole of religion is contained in the Sacraments, and there are
consequently no other religious acts than those which are performed
in Baptism and the Lord’s Supper;
then
I grant that the entire purport and positive result of my work are
bathing, eating, and drinking, since this work is nothing but a
faithful, rigid, historico-philosophical analysis of religion—the
revelation of religion to itself, the
awakening of religion to self-consciousness.I
say an
historico-philosophical
analysis, in distinction from a merely
historical
analysis of Christianity. The historical critic—such a one, for
example, as Daumer or Ghillany—shows that the Lord’s Supper is a
rite lineally descended from the ancient cultus of human sacrifice;
that once, instead of bread and wine, real human flesh and blood
were
partaken. I, on the contrary, take as the object of my analysis and
reduction only the Christian significance of the rite, that view of
it which is
sanctioned
Christianity, and I proceed on the supposition that only
that significance
which a dogma or institution has in Christianity (of course in
ancient Christianity, not in modern), whether it may present itself
in other religions or not, is also the
true origin
of that dogma or institution
in so far
as it is
Christian.
Again, the historical critic, as, for example, Lützelberger, shows
that the narratives of the miracles of Christ resolve themselves
into
contradictions and absurdities, that they are later fabrications,
and
that consequently Christ was no miracle-worker, nor, in general,
that
which he is represented to be in the Bible. I, on the other hand,
do
not inquire what the real, natural Christ was or may have been in
distinction from what he has been made or has become in
Supernaturalism; on the contrary, I accept the Christ of religion,
but I show that this superhuman being is nothing else than a
product
and reflex of the supernatural human mind. I do not ask whether
this
or that, or any miracle
can
happen or not; I only show
what
miracle
is,
and I show it not
à priori,
but by examples of miracles narrated in the Bible as real events;
in
doing so, however, I answer or rather preclude the question as to
the
possibility or reality of necessity of miracle. Thus much
concerning
the distinction between me and the historical critics who have
attacked Christianity. As regards my relation to Strauss and Bruno
Bauer, in company with whom I am constantly named, I merely point
out
here that the distinction between our works is sufficiently
indicated
by the distinction between their objects, which is implied even in
the title-page. Bauer takes for the object of his criticism the
evangelical history,
i.e.,
biblical Christianity, or rather biblical theology; Strauss, the
System of Christian Doctrine and the Life of Jesus (which may also
be
included under the title of Christian Doctrine),
i.e.,
dogmatic Christianity, or rather dogmatic theology; I, Christianity
in general,
i.e.,
the Christian
religion,
and consequently only Christian philosophy or theology. Hence I
take
my citations chiefly from men in whom Christianity was not merely a
theory or a dogma, not merely theology, but religion. My principal
theme is Christianity, is Religion, as it is the
immediate object,
the
immediate nature,
of man. Erudition and philosophy are to me only the
means
by which I bring to light the treasure hid in man.I
must further mention that the circulation which my work has had
amongst the public at large was neither desired nor expected by me.
It is true that I have always taken as the standard of the mode of
teaching and writing, not the abstract, particular, professional
philosopher, but universal man, that I have regarded
man
as the criterion of truth, and not this or that founder of a
system,
and have from the first placed the highest excellence of the
philosopher in this, that he abstains, both as a man and as an
author, from the ostentation of philosophy,
i.e.,
that he is a philosopher only in reality, not formally, that he is
a
quiet philosopher, not a loud and still less a brawling one. Hence,
in all my works, as well as in the present one, I have made the
utmost clearness, simplicity, and definiteness a law to myself, so
that they may be understood, at least in the main, by every
cultivated and thinking man. But notwithstanding this, my work can
be
appreciated and fully understood only by the scholar, that is to
say,
by the scholar who loves truth, who is capable of forming a
judgment,
who is above the notions and prejudices of the learned and
unlearned
vulgar; for although a thoroughly independent production, it has
yet
its necessary logical basis in history. I very frequently refer to
this or that historical phenomenon without expressly designating
it,
thinking this superfluous; and such references can be understood by
the scholar alone. Thus, for example, in the very first chapter,
where I develop the necessary consequences of the standpoint of
Feeling, I allude to Jacobi and Schleiermacher; in the second
chapter
I allude chiefly to Kantism, Scepticism, Theism, Materialism and
Pantheism; in the chapter on the “Standpoint of Religion,” where
I discuss the contradictions between the religious or theological
and
the physical or natural-philosophical view of Nature, I refer to
philosophy in the age of orthodoxy, and especially to the
philosophy
of Descartes and Leibnitz, in which this contradiction presents
itself in a peculiarly characteristic manner. The reader,
therefore,
who is unacquainted with the historical facts and ideas presupposed
in my work, will fail to perceive on what my arguments and ideas
hinge; no wonder if my positions often appear to him baseless,
however firm the footing on which they stand. It is true that the
subject of my work is of universal human interest; moreover, its
fundamental ideas, though not in the form in which they are here
expressed, or in which they could be expressed under existing
circumstances, will one day become the common property of mankind:
for nothing is opposed to them in the present day but empty,
powerless illusions and prejudices in contradiction with the true
nature of man. But in considering this subject in the first
instance,
I was under the necessity of treating it as a matter of science, of
philosophy; and in rectifying the aberrations of Religion,
Theology,
and Speculation, I was naturally obliged to use their expressions,
and even to appear to speculate, or—which is the same thing—to
turn theologian myself, while I nevertheless only analyse
speculation,
i.e.,
reduce theology to anthropology. My work, as I said before,
contains,
and applies in the concrete, the principle of a new philosophy
suited—not to the schools, but—to man. Yes, it contains that
principle, but only by
evolving
it out of the very core of religion; hence, be it said in passing,
the new philosophy can no longer, like the old Catholic and modern
Protestant scholasticism, fall into the temptation to prove its
agreement with religion by its agreement with Christian dogmas; on
the contrary, being evolved from the nature of religion, it has in
itself the true essence of religion,—is, in its very quality as a
philosophy, a religion also. But a work which considers ideas in
their genesis and explains and demonstrates them in strict
sequence,
is, by the very form which this purpose imposes upon it, unsuited
to
popular reading.Lastly,
as a supplement to this work with regard to many apparently
unvindicated positions, I refer to my articles in the
Deutsches Jahrbuch,
January and February 1842, to my critiques and
Charakteristiken des modernen After-christenthums,
in previous numbers of the same periodical, and to my earlier
works,
especially the following:—P.
Bayle. Ein Beitrag zur Geschichte der Philosophie und
Menschheit,
Ausbach, 1838, and
Philosophie und Christenthum,
Mannheim, 1839. In these works I have sketched, with a few sharp
touches, the historical solution of Christianity, and have shown
that
Christianity has in fact long vanished, not only from the reason
but
from the life of mankind, that it is nothing more than a
fixed idea,
in flagrant contradiction with our fire and life assurance
companies,
our railroads and steam-carriages, our picture and sculpture
galleries, our military and industrial schools, our theatres and
scientific museums.LUDWIG
FEUERBACH.1The
opening paragraphs of this Preface are omitted, as having too
specific a reference to transient German polemics to interest the
English reader. ↑2For
example, in considering the sacraments, I limit myself to two;
for in
the strictest sense (see Luther, T. xvii. p. 558), there are no
more. ↑