Aquinas Ethicus - Thomas Aquinas - E-Book

Aquinas Ethicus E-Book

Thomas Aquinas

0,0
0,99 €

oder
-100%
Sammeln Sie Punkte in unserem Gutscheinprogramm und kaufen Sie E-Books und Hörbücher mit bis zu 100% Rabatt.
Mehr erfahren.
Beschreibung

The Sovereign Pontiff, Leo XIII., in his Encyclical on Scholastic Philosophy, writes as follows: “Let the teachers whom you shall discreetly choose make it their aim to instil the doctrine of Thomas Aquinas into the minds of their scholars, and to set in a clear light his solidity and excellence above other authors. . . . But lest supposititious utterances be taken for true, or adulterate for genuine, see to it that the wisdom of Thomas be drunk in from his own streams.”

Das E-Book können Sie in Legimi-Apps oder einer beliebigen App lesen, die das folgende Format unterstützen:

EPUB
Bewertungen
0,0
0
0
0
0
0
Mehr Informationen
Mehr Informationen
Legimi prüft nicht, ob Rezensionen von Nutzern stammen, die den betreffenden Titel tatsächlich gekauft oder gelesen/gehört haben. Wir entfernen aber gefälschte Rezensionen.



AQUINAS ETHICUS

by Thomas Aquinas

Published 2018 by Blackmore Dennett

All rights reserved. This book or any portion thereof may not be reproduced or used in any manner whatsoever without the express written permission of the publisher except for the use of brief quotations in a book review.

Please visit us at www.blackmoredennett.com to see our latest offerings.

Thank you for your purchase. If you enjoyed this work, please leave us a comment.

1 2 3 4 10 8 7 6 5 00 000

TABLE OF CONTENTS

 

First Division of the Second Part

Commonly called Prima Secundæ.

QUESTION I.: OF THE LAST END OF MAN IN GENERAL.

QUESTION II.: OF THE OBJECT IN WHICH MAN’S HAPPINESS CONSISTS.

QUESTION III.: WHAT IS HAPPINESS?

QUESTION IV.: OF THINGS REQUISITE FOR HAPPINESS.

QUESTION V.: OF THE ATTAINMENT OF HAPPINESS.

QUESTION VI.: OF THE VOLUNTARY AND THE INVOLUNTARY.

QUESTION VII.: OF THE CIRCUMSTANCES OF HUMAN ACTS.

QUESTION VIII.: OF THE WILL AND ITS OBJECTS.

QUESTION XII.: OF INTENTION.

QUESTION XIII.: OF ELECTION, OR CHOICE OF MEANS.

QUESTION XVIII.: OF THE GOOD OR EVIL OF HUMAN ACTS IN GENERAL.

QUESTION XIX.: OF THE GOOD AND EVIL OF THE INTERIOR ACT OF THE WILL.

QUESTION XX.: OF THE GOOD AND EVIL OF EXTERIOR HUMAN ACTS.

QUESTION XXI.: OF THE PROPERTIES CONSEQUENT UPON HUMAN ACTS CONSIDERED AS GOOD OR EVIL.

QUESTION XXII.: OF THE SUBJECT OF THE PASSIONS.

QUESTION XXIII.: OF THE DIFFERENCE OF PASSIONS ONE FROM ANOTHER.

QUESTION XXIV.: OF GOOD AND EVIL IN PASSIONS.

QUESTION XXVI.: OF LOVE.

QUESTION XXVII.: OF THE CAUSE OF LOVE.

QUESTION XXVIII.: OF THE EFFECTS OF LOVE.

QUESTION XXIX.: OF HATRED.

QUESTION XXX.: OF DESIRE.

QUESTION XXXI.: OF DELIGHT, OR PLEASURE.

QUESTION XXXII.: OF THE CAUSE OF PLEASURE.

QUESTION XXXIII.: OF THE EFFECTS OF PLEASURE.

QUESTION XXXIV.: OF GOOD AND EVIL IN PLEASURES.

QUESTION XXXV.: OF PAIN AND SORROW IN THEMSELVES.

QUESTION XXXVI.: OF THE CAUSES OF PAIN.

QUESTION XXXVIII.: OF REMEDIES FOR SORROW OR PAIN.

QUESTION XXXIX.: OF THE GOOD AND EVIL OF SORROW OR PAIN.

QUESTION XL.: OF HOPE.

QUESTION XLI.: OF FEAR IN ITSELF.

QUESTION XLII.: OF THE OBJECT OF FEAR.

QUESTION XLIV.: OF THE EFFECTS OF FEAR.

QUESTION XLV.: OF FIERY DARING.

QUESTION XLVI.: OF ANGER AS IT IS IN ITSELF.

QUESTION XLVII.: OF THE EFFICIENT CAUSE OF ANGER.

QUESTION XLVIII.: OF THE EFFECTS OF ANGER.

QUESTION XLIX.: OF HABITS IN GENERAL.

QUESTION L.: OF THE SUBJECT OF HABITS.

QUESTION LI.: OF THE GENERATING CAUSE OF HABITS.

QUESTION LII.: OF THE INCREASE OF HABITS.

QUESTION LIII.: OF THE DESTRUCTION AND DIMINUTION OF HABITS.

QUESTION LV.: OF VIRTUES IN THEIR ESSENCE.

QUESTION LVI.: OF THE SUBJECT OF VIRTUE.

QUESTION LVII.: OF THE VARIOUS INTELLECTUAL VIRTUES.

QUESTION LVIII.: OF THE DISTINCTION OF MORAL VIRTUES FROM INTELLECTUAL.

QUESTION LIX.: OF MORAL VIRTUES IN THEIR RELATION TO THE PASSIONS.

QUESTION LXI.: OF THE CARDINAL VIRTUES.

QUESTION LXII.: OF THE THEOLOGICAL VIRTUES.

QUESTION LXIII.: OF THE CAUSE OF VIRTUES.

QUESTION LXIV.: OF THE MEAN OF VIRTUES.

QUESTION LXV.: OF THE CONNEXION OF VIRTUE WITH VIRTUE.

QUESTION LXXI.: OF VICES AND SINS IN THEMSELVES.

QUESTION LXXII.: OF THE DISTINCTION BETWEEN SIN AND SIN.

QUESTION LXXIII.: OF THE COMPARISON OF SIN WITH SIN.

QUESTION LXXIV.: OF THE SUBJECT OF SINS.

QUESTION LXXV.: OF THE CAUSES OF SIN IN GENERAL.

QUESTION LXXVI.: OF THE CAUSES OF SIN IN PARTICULAR.

QUESTION LXXVII.: OF THE CAUSE OF SIN ON THE PART OF THE SENSITIVE APPETITE.

QUESTION LXXVIII.: OF MALICE AS A CAUSE OF SIN.

QUESTION LXXXIV.: OF ONE SIN BEING THE CAUSE OF ANOTHER SIN.

QUESTION LXXXVI.: OF THE STAIN OF SIN.

QUESTION LXXXVII.: OF LIABILITY TO PUNISHMENT.

QUESTION LXXXVIII.: OF VENIAL AND MORTAL SIN.

QUESTION XC.: OF LAWS.

QUESTION XCI.: OF THE VARIETY OF LAWS.

QUESTION XCII.: OF THE EFFECTS OF LAW.

QUESTION XCIII.: OF THE ETERNAL LAW.

QUESTION XCIV.: OF THE NATURAL LAW.

QUESTION XCV.: OF HUMAN LAW.

QUESTION XCVI.: OF THE AUTHORITY OF HUMAN LAW.

QUESTION XCVII.: OF CHANGE OF LAWS.

QUESTION C.: OF THE MORAL PRECEPTS OF THE OLD LAW.

Second Division, or Secunda Secundæ

QUESTION I.: OF FAITH.

QUESTION II.: OF THE ACT OF FAITH.

QUESTION III.: OF THE EXTERIOR ACT OF FAITH.

QUESTION IV.: OF THE VIRTUE OF FAITH.

QUESTION V.: OF PERSONS HAVING FAITH.

QUESTION VI.: OF THE CAUSE OF FAITH.

QUESTION X.: OF UNBELIEF IN GENERAL.

QUESTION XI.: OF HERESY.

QUESTION XII.: OF APOSTASY.

QUESTION XIII.: OF THE SIN OF BLASPHEMY.

QUESTION XVII.: OF HOPE.

QUESTION XVIII.: OF THE SUBJECT OF HOPE.

QUESTION XIX.: OF THE GIFT OF FEAR.

QUESTION XX.: OF DESPAIR.

QUESTION XXI.: OF PRESUMPTION.

QUESTION XXIII.: OF CHARITY IN ITSELF.

QUESTION XXIV.: OF THE SUBJECT OF CHARITY.

QUESTION XXV.: OF THE OBJECT OF CHARITY.

QUESTION XXVI.: OF THE ORDER TO BE OBSERVED IN CHARITY.

QUESTION XXVII.: OF THE PRINCIPAL ACT OF CHARITY, WHICH IS LOVE.

QUESTION XXVIII.: OF JOY.

QUESTION XXIX.: OF PEACE.

QUESTION XXXI.: OF DOING GOOD TO OTHERS.

QUESTION XXXII.: OF ALMSGIVING.

QUESTION XXXIII.: OF FRATERNAL CORRECTION.

QUESTION XXXIV.: OF HATRED.

QUESTION XXXV.: OF SLOTH.

QUESTION XXXVI.: OF ENVY.

QUESTION XXXVII.: OF DISCORD.

QUESTION XL.: OF WAR.

QUESTION XLI.: OF ASSAULT AND BATTERY.

QUESTION XLII.: OF SEDITION.

QUESTION XLIII.: OF SCANDAL.

QUESTION XLIV.: OF THE PRECEPTS OF CHARITY.  [St. Matt. xxii. 36—40.]

QUESTION XLVI.: OF STUPIDITY.

QUESTION XLVII.: OF PRUDENCE.

QUESTION XLVIII.: OF THE PARTS OF PRUDENCE.

QUESTION LV.: OF THE PRUDENCE OF THE FLESH.

QUESTION LVII.: OF RIGHT.

QUESTION LVIII.: OF JUSTICE.

QUESTION LIX.: OF INJUSTICE.

QUESTION LX.: OF JUDGMENT.

QUESTION LXI.: OF THE PARTS OF JUSTICE.

QUESTION LXII.: OF RESTITUTION.

QUESTION LXIII.: OF THE RESPECTING OF PERSONS.

QUESTION LXIV.: OF HOMICIDE.

QUESTION LXV.: OF MUTILATION OF MEMBERS.

QUESTION LXVI.: OF THEFT AND ROBBERY.

QUESTION LXVII.: OF INJUSTICE IN A JUDGE.

QUESTION LXVIII.: OF WHAT RELATES TO AN UNJUST ACCUSATION.

QUESTION LXIX.: OF SINS AGAINST JUSTICE ON THE PART OF THE ACCUSED.

QUESTION LXX.: OF INJUSTICE IN THE PERSON OF THE WITNESS.

QUESTION LXXI.: OF INJUSTICE ON THE PART OF COUNSEL AT LAW.

QUESTION LXXII.: OF INJURIOUS LANGUAGE OUT OF COURT, AND FIRST OF CONTUMELY.

QUESTION LXXIII.: OF DETRACTION.

QUESTION LXXIV.: OF MISCHIEF-MAKING.

QUESTION LXXVI.: OF CURSING.

QUESTION LXXVII.: OF FRAUDULENT DEALING IN BUYING AND SELLING.

QUESTION LXXVIII.: OF THE SIN OF USURY THAT IS COMMITTED IN LOANS.

QUESTION LXXIX.: OF THE INTEGRAL PARTS OF JUSTICE, WHICH ARE TO DO GOOD AND TURN AWAY FROM EVIL.

QUESTION LXXX.: OF THE POTENTIAL PARTS OF JUSTICE.

QUESTION LXXXI.: OF RELIGION.

QUESTION LXXXII.: OF DEVOTION.

QUESTION LXXXIII.: OF PRAYER.

QUESTION LXXXIV.: OF THE EXTERIOR ACTS OF DIVINE WORSHIP.

QUESTION LXXXV.: OF SACRIFICE.

QUESTION LXXXVI.: OF OFFERINGS.

QUESTION LXXXVIII.: OF A VOW WHEREBY SOMETHING IS PROMISED TO GOD.

QUESTION LXXXIX.: OF OATHS.

QUESTION XCI.: OF THE TAKING OF THE DIVINE NAME TO INVOKE IT IN PRAYER OR PRAISE.

QUESTION XCII.: OF VICES OPPOSED TO RELIGION, AND FIRST OF SUPERSTITION.

QUESTION XCIII.: OF THE SPECIES OF SUPERSTITION; AND FIRST OF SUPERSTITION BY UNDUE WORSHIP OF THE TRUE GOD.

QUESTION XCIV.: OF IDOLATRY.

QUESTION XCV.: OF THE SUPERSTITION OF DIVINATION.

QUESTION XCVI.: OF SUPERSTITIOUS OBSERVANCES.

QUESTION XCVII.: OF TEMPTING GOD.

QUESTION XCVIII.: OF PERJURY.

QUESTION XCIX.: OF SACRILEGE.

QUESTION C.: OF SIMONY.

QUESTION CI.: OF NATURAL AFFECTION.

QUESTION CIV.: OF OBEDIENCE.

QUESTION CVI.: OF GRATITUDE.

QUESTION CVII.: OF INGRATITUDE.

QUESTION CVIII.: OF VENGEANCE.

QUESTION CIX.: OF TRUTHFULNESS.

QUESTION CX.: OF VICES OPPOSED TO TRUTHFULNESS, AND FIRST OF LYING.

QUESTION CXI.: OF SIMULATION AND HYPOCRISY.

QUESTION CXII.: OF BOASTING.

QUESTION CXIII.: OF SELF-DEPRECIATION.

QUESTION CXIV.: OF THE FRIENDLINESS THAT IS CALLED AFFABILITY.

QUESTION CXV.: OF FLATTERY.

QUESTION CXVI.: OF THE SPIRIT OF CONTRADICTION.

QUESTION CXVII.: OF LIBERALITY.

QUESTION CXVIII.: OF COVETOUSNESS.

QUESTION CXIX.: OF PRODIGALITY.

QUESTION CXX.: OF EQUITY.

QUESTION CXXIII.: OF FORTITUDE.

QUESTION CXXIV.: OF MARTYRDOM.

QUESTION CXXV.: OF FEAR.

QUESTION CXXVI.: OF INSENSIBILITY TO FEAR.

QUESTION CXXVII.: OF FIERY DARING.

QUESTION CXXVIII.: OF THE PARTS OF FORTITUDE.

QUESTION CXXIX.: OF MAGNANIMITY.

QUESTION CXXX.: OF PRESUMPTION.

QUESTION CXXXI.: OF AMBITION.

QUESTION CXXXII.: OF VAINGLORY.

QUESTION CXXXIII.: OF PUSILLANIMITY.

QUESTION CXXXIV.: OF MUNIFICENCE.

QUESTION CXXXV.: OF PETTY ECONOMY.

QUESTION CXXXVI.: OF PATIENCE.

QUESTION CXXXVII.: OF PERSEVERANCE.

QUESTION CXLI.: OF TEMPERANCE.

QUESTION CXLII.: OF VICES OPPOSED TO TEMPERANCE.

QUESTION CXLIII.: OF THE PARTS OF TEMPERANCE IN GENERAL.

QUESTION CXLV.: OF PROPRIETY.

QUESTION CXLVI.: OF ABSTINENCE.

QUESTION CXLVII.: OF FASTING.

QUESTION CXLVIII.: OF GLUTTONY.

QUESTION CXLIX.: OF SOBRIETY.

QUESTION CL.: OF DRUNKENNESS.

QUESTION CLI.: OF CHASTITY.

QUESTION CLII.: OF VIRGINITY.

QUESTION CLIII.: OF THE VICE OF LUXURY.

QUESTION CLIV.: OF THE PARTS OF LUXURY.

QUESTION CLV.: OF THE POTENTIAL PARTS OF TEMPERANCE; AND FIRST OF CONTINENCE.

QUESTION CLVI.: OF INCONTINENCE.

QUESTION CLVII.: OF CLEMENCY AND MEEKNESS.

QUESTION CLVIII.: OF IRASCIBILITY.

QUESTION CLIX.: OF CRUELTY.

QUESTION CLXI.: OF HUMILITY.

QUESTION CLXII.: OF PRIDE.

QUESTION CLXVI.: OF STUDIOUSNESS.

QUESTION CLXVII.: OF CURIOSITY.

QUESTION CLXVIII.: OF MODESTY, OR DECORUM, IN THE OUTWARD MOVEMENTS OF THE BODY.

QUESTION CLXIX.: OF MODESTY IN DRESS.

QUESTION CLXXXII.: OF THE COMPARISON OF THE ACTIVE LIFE WITH THE CONTEMPLATIVE.

QUESTION CLXXXIII.: OF OFFICES AND VARIOUS STATES OF MEN IN GENERAL.

QUESTION CLXXXIV.: OF WHAT RELATES TO THE STATE OF PERFECTION IN GENERAL.

QUESTION CLXXXVI.: OF THE THINGS IN WHICH THE RELIGIOUS STATE PROPERLY CONSISTS.

QUESTION CLXXXVII.: OF THE THINGS PROPER FOR RELIGIOUS TO DO.

QUESTION CLXXXVIII.: OF THE VARIETY OF RELIGIOUS ORDERS.

QUESTION CLXXXIX.: OF THE ENTRY INTO RELIGION.

 

 

First Division of the Second Part

Commonly called Prima Secundæ.

QUESTION I.: OF THE LAST END OF MAN IN GENERAL.

Article I.—Is it proper to man to act for an end?

R. Of the actions done by man, those alone are properly called human,which are proper to man as man. Now man differs from irrational creatures in this, that he is master of his own acts. Wherefore those acts alone are properly called human, whereof man is master. But man is master of his own acts by reason and will: hence free-will is said to be a function of will and reason. Those actions, therefore, are properly called human, which proceed from a deliberate will. Any other actions attributable to man may indeed be styled actions of man, but not properly human actions, since they are not of man  as he is man. Now it is clear that all the actions that proceed from any power are caused by that power acting in reference to its object. But the object of the will is some end in the shape of good. Therefore all human actions must be for an end.

§ 1. The end, though it is last in execution, is first in the intention of the agent, and in this way stands as a cause.

§ 3. Such actions as when man moves foot or hand, while thinking of other things, or strokes his beard, are not properly human, because they do not proceed from the deliberation of the reason, which is the proper principle of human actions.

Article IV.—Is there any last end of human conduct?

R. In ends there is found a twofold order, to wit, the order of intention and the order of execution, and in both orders there must be some first point. That which is first in the order of intention is a sort of principle moving the desire: take that principle away, and desire would have nothing to move it. The moving principle of the execution is that from whence the work begins: take away that moving principle, and none would begin to work at anything. Now the moving principle of the intention is the last end: the moving principle of the execution is the first step in the way of means to the end. Thus, then, on neither side is it possible to go on to infinity: because, if there were no last end, nothing would be desired, nor any action have a term, nor would the intention of the  agent rest. On the other hand, if there were no first step in the means to the end, no one would begin to work at anything, and deliberation would never terminate, but go on to infinity.

Article V.—Can one man have several ultimate ends?

R. It is impossible for the will of one man at the same time to go out to several diverse objects as to so many different last ends. The reason may be assigned thus. Since every being seeks its own perfection, a man seeks that as his last end which he seeks as his perfect and crowning good. The last end therefore must so fill the whole of the man’s desire as to leave nothing to be desired beyond it. This cannot be, if anything further is required to the perfection of that end. Therefore desire cannot go out to two things as if each were its perfect good.

§ 1. To Augustine’s saying, “Some have placed the last end of man in four things, pleasure, repose, the goods of nature, and virtue,” it is to be said that all these several objects are regarded in the light of one perfect good constituted out of them, by those who have placed in them their last end.

§ 3. The power of the will does not extend to making things opposite and irreconcilable coexist, as they would coexist, if the will could tend to several diverse objects as to so many last ends.

§ 4. That wherein a man rests as in his last end dominates his desire, because therefrom he takes rules of conduct for his whole life: whence it is said  of gluttons, “Whose god is their belly,” because they place their last end in the pleasures of the table. But, as is said: “No man can serve two masters,” two, that is, not in concert with one another. Therefore it is impossible for one man to have several ultimate ends not in harmony with one another.

Article VI.—Is everything that a man wills, willed for the sake of the last end?

R. It needs must be that all things that a man desires are desired for the sake of the last end. Whatever a man desires, he desires in the light of a good thing. If it is not desired as perfect good, which is the last end, it must be desired as tending to perfect good, because always the commencement of a thing is directed to the completion thereof, as is apparent both in things of nature and in things of art, and thus every commencement of perfection is directed to the attainment of perfection in its full measure, which is the achievement of the last end.

§ 1. Actions done in jest are not referred to any external end, but are simply directed to the good of the author of the jest, his delight or recreation. But the full measure of the good of man is found in his last end.

§ 2. Speculative science, being desired as some sort of good by the student of it, is comprehended under that complete and perfect good which is the last end.

§ 3. It is not necessary for one to be always thinking of the last end in every desire and in every work; but the efficacy of the first intention, which is made in view of the last end, remains in every desire of everything, even without any actual thought of the last end: just as it is not necessary in walking along a road to think at every step of the place whither you are going.

§ 4. Augustine says: “That is our final good, which is loved for its own sake, and all other things for the sake of it.”

Article VII.—Is the last end of all men one and the same?

R. We may speak of the last end in two ways: in one way, of the last end itself; in another way, of that in which the character of the last end is found. As regards the last end itself, all agree in desiring the last end, because all desire the fulness of their own well-being, in which full well-being the last end consists. But as regards that in which the character of the last end is found, all men do not agree in their last end. Some seek riches as their complete and final good; others seek pleasure; others other things; just as to every taste deliciousness is pleasant, but to some men most pleasant is the deliciousness of wine, to others the deliciousness of honey, and so of the rest. Nevertheless, that must absolutely be most pleasant, with which he is best pleased who has the best taste; and in like manner that good must be most complete, which is  pursued as his last end by him whose affections are best in order.

§ 1. They who sin turn away from that in which the character of the last end is truly found, but not from the simple intention of the last end, which they mistakenly seek in the wrong things.

§ 2. The difference of interests and pursuits in life between man and man is due to the diversity of things in which the character of the final good is sought.

QUESTION II.: OF THE OBJECT IN WHICH MAN’S HAPPINESS CONSISTS.

Article I.—Does happiness consist in riches?

R. It is impossible for the happiness of man to consist in riches. For riches are of two sorts, as the Philosopher says, natural and artificial. Naturalriches are all those aids which go to the supply of natural wants, like meat and drink, clothing, means of transport, habitation, and the rest. Artificialriches take the form of money, something that is no aid to nature in itself, but is an invention of human contrivance for the convenience of exchange, as a measure of things saleable. Now clearly the happiness of man cannot be in the possession of natural riches. For such riches are eligible for the sustenance of man’s nature, and therefore cannot be  themselves the last end of man, but rather man is the end to which they are referred. Whence in the order of nature all such things are below man, and are made for man, as it is said: “Thou hast subjected all things beneath his feet.” Artificial riches, on the other hand, are not eligible except for the sake of those that are natural. They would not be sought at all except for the fact that with them things are bought that are necessary for the uses of life. Much less therefore can they bear the character of a final end.

§ 1. “All” material “things obey money,” so far as the multitude of fools is concerned, who know only material things, which can be acquired by money. But an estimate of human goods should not be taken by the judgment of fools, but by that of wise men, as an estimate of palatable and unpalatable food is taken by the judgment of those whose sense of taste is in good order.

§ 2. To the words of the Philosopher, “Money was invented on purpose to be a sort of surety for having in exchange for it whatever man can desire,” it is to be said that all saleable articles may be had for money, but not spiritual goods: they cannot be sold. Hence it is said: “What doth it profit a fool to have money, when he cannot buy wisdom?”

§ 3. The desire of natural riches is not boundless, because a certain measure of riches is sufficient for nature: but the desire of artificial riches is boundless, not however in the same way as the desire of the supreme good. For the more perfectly  the supreme good is possessed, the more it is loved, and all things else despised. But with the desire of riches and all other temporal goods the contrary is the case: for when they are got, what is already in hand is despised, and something else desired, because their insufficiency is better recognized when they are possessed. And this very fact is a proof of their imperfection, and that the supreme good consists not in them.

Article II.—Does man’s happiness consist in honours?

R. It is impossible that happiness should consist in honour. For honour is paid to a person for some excellence of his, and so is a sign and testimony of that excellence which is in the person honoured. Now a man’s excellence is taken to obtain especially in point of happiness, which is the perfect good of man, and of the parts of happiness, that is, in point of those goods which are some participation of happiness. Therefore honour may indeed follow upon happiness, but happiness cannot consist principally in honour.

§ 1. Honour is not the reward of virtue for which the virtuous work, but they receive honour from men in lieu of a reward, inasmuch as men have nothing greater to give them. But the true reward of virtue is happiness itself, and for that the virtuous work; whereas, if they worked for honour, it would not be virtue but rather ambition.

§ 2. Honour is due to God, and to beings of high excellence, as a sign or testimony of pre-existent  excellence, not that the mere honour makes them excellent.

§ 3. As honour attends upon happiness, it follows from the natural desire of happiness that men have a prevailing desire of honour; hence they seek especially to be honoured by the wise, upon whose judgment they believe themselves to be excellent or fortunate.

Article III.—Does man’s happiness consist in fame and glory?

R. It is impossible for the happiness of man to consist in fame or human glory. For glory is nothing else than “clear notoriety with praise,” as Augustine says. Now the thing known stands in different relations to divine and to human knowledge. Human knowledge is caused by the things known, but divine knowledge is the cause of the things known. Hence the perfection of human good, which is called happiness, cannot be caused by human knowledge or notoriety amongst men, but rather men’s knowledge of another man’s happiness proceeds from and is in a manner caused by that same happiness, either in its initial or in its perfect state. But the good of man depends upon the knowledge of God as upon its cause; and therefore upon the glory which is with God human happiness depends as upon its cause. It is further  to be considered that human knowledge is liable to many deceptions, especially as to points of detail in such a matter as human acts; and therefore human glory is frequently fallacious. But because God cannot be deceived, the glory that is of Him is ever true; therefore it is said: “He is approved whom God commendeth.”

§ 2. As for that good which comes of fame and glory in the knowledge of many, we say that, if the knowledge be true, the good thereof must be derived from a previous good, existing in the man himself, and so presupposes perfect happiness, or at least the commencement of it. But if the knowledge be a false impression, it is not in harmony with fact, and in the man celebrated and famous at that rate no good is found.

Article IV.—Does man’s happiness consist in power?

R. It is impossible for happiness to consist in power, and that for two reasons. First, because power is an initiative, but happiness a last and final end. Secondly, because power is susceptible of good and evil, but happiness is the proper and perfect good of man. Hence it were more possible for some happiness to consist in the good use of power, which is by virtue, than in power itself.

§ 1. The divine power is its own goodness: hence God cannot use His power otherwise than well. But this is not the case in men. Hence it is not sufficient for happiness that man be likened  unto God in power, unless he be likened to Him also in goodness.

§ 2. As it is the height of good that one should use power well in the government of many, so it is the lowest depth of evil if one uses power ill. Thus power is susceptible of good and of evil.

§ 3. Slavery is an obstacle to the good use of power, and therefore men naturally shun it, not as though the highest good consisted in power.

Four general reasons may be brought to show that in none of the above-mentioned exterior goods does happiness consist.

The first is that, happiness being the supreme good of man, no evil is compatible with it, but all the aforesaid things may be found in good men and evil men alike.

The second reason is that, whereas it is of the essence of happiness to be all in all by itself, it needs must be that, happiness once gained, no needful good is wanting to man; but after the gaining of each of the advantages above-mentioned, there may still be many needful good things wanting to man, as wisdom, bodily health, and the like.

Third reason, because whereas happiness is perfect good, it is impossible for any evil to come to any one from happiness, which is not true of the things in question, for it is said, “Riches are sometimes kept to the sorrow of their owner,” and in like manner of the other things.

The fourth reason is, because man is directed to  happiness by interior principles, since he is directed to it by nature, but all the four goods above-mentioned are rather from exterior causes, and generally from fortune, whence they are called “goods of fortune.” Hence it is manifest that happiness nowise consists in the aforesaid things.

Article V.—Does man’s happiness consist in any good of the body?

R. It is impossible for the happiness of man to consist in goods of the body, for two reasons. First of all because it is impossible for that which is referred to something else as to its last end, to have its end in the preservation of its own being. Hence a captain does not intend as a last end the preservation of the ship entrusted to him, because the ship is referred to something else as its end, namely, navigation. But as a ship is given over to the captain to direct its course, so man is given over to his own will and reason, as is said: “God made man from the beginning, and left him in the hand of his own counsel.” But it is clear that man is referred to something as to an end, for man is not the supreme good. Hence it is impossible that the last end of human reason and will should be the preservation of human existence.

Secondly because, granted that the end of human reason and will were the preservation of human existence, still it could not be said that the end of man was any good of the body. For the being of man consists of soul and body, and while the  being of the body depends on the soul, at the same time the being of the human soul does not depend on the body: indeed, the body is for the soul, as the matter is for the form, and as instruments are for him that uses them to do his work with: hence all goods of the body are referred to goods of the soul as to their end. Hence it is impossible that happiness, the ultimate end, should consist in goods of the body.

Article VI.—Does man’s happiness consist in pleasure?

R. Because bodily delights are better known, they have arrogated to themselves the name of pleasures. Still happiness does not consist principally in them. In everything, what belongs to the essence is distinguished from the proprium consequent upon the essence, as in man his being a mortal rational animal is distinguished from his being risible. We must notice accordingly that every delight is a sort of propriumconsequent upon happiness, or upon some portion of happiness. For a man is delighted at this, that he has hold either in reality, or in hope, or at least in memory, of some good that suits him. Now that suitable good, if it is perfect, is none other than the happiness of man: but if it is imperfect, it is a participation in happiness, proximate, or remote, or at least apparent. Hence it is manifest that not even the delight which follows perfect good is the essence and core of happiness, but is consequent upon happiness after the manner of a proprium.

But bodily pleasure cannot follow perfect good even in the aforesaid way, for it follows that good which is apprehended by sense; but no bodily good apprehended by sense can be the perfect good of man, but is a trifle in comparison with the good of the soul. Thus bodily pleasure is neither happiness itself nor a proprium of happiness.

§ 1. The desire of good and the desire of delight stand on the same footing, delight being nothing else than the repose of desire in good. Hence, as good is desired for itself, so also is delight desired for itself, if by for we mean the final cause: but if we consider the motive cause, delight is desirable for something else, namely, for the good which is the object of delight, and which consequently is the principle that starts it and gives it its form. For by this is delight desirable, that it is a repose in a longed for good.

§ 2. The vehemence of the desire of sensible delight arises from the operations of the senses being more readily perceptible, as being the beginnings of our knowledge: hence also sensible delights are gone after by the greater number of men.

§ 3. All men desire delights in the same way in which they desire good; and yet the delight is desired by reason of the good, and not the other way about. Hence it does not follow that delight is good of itself and the greatest of goods; but that every delight is consequent upon some good, and some delight is consequent upon that which is good of itself and the greatest of goods.

Article VII.

§ 3. Happiness itself, being a perfection of the soul, is a good inherent in the soul: but that in which happiness consists, or the object that makes one happy, is something outside the soul.

Article VIII.—Does man’s happiness consist in any created good?

R. It is impossible for the happiness of man to be in any created good. For happiness is perfect good, which entirely appeases desire: otherwise it would not be the last end, if something still remained to be desired. But the object of the will is universal good, as the object of the intellect is universal truth. Hence it is clear that nothing can set the will of man to rest but universal good, which is not found in anything created, but in God alone. Hence God alone can fill the heart of man.

§ 3. Created good is not less than what a man is capable of as a good intrinsic to and inherent in him; but it is less than the good that he is capable of as an object, for that is infinite.

QUESTION III.: WHAT IS HAPPINESS?

Article I.—Is happiness something uncreated?

R. The word end has two meanings. In one meaning it stands for the thing itself which we desire to gain: thus the miser’s end is money. In another meaning it stands for the mere attainment, or possession, or use, or enjoyment of the thing desired, as if one should say that the possession of money is the miser’s end, or the enjoyment of something pleasant the end of the sensualist. In the first meaning of the word, therefore, the end of man is the Uncreated Good, namely God, who alone of His infinite goodness can perfectly satisfy the will of man. But according to the second meaning the last end of man is something created, existing in himself, which is nothing else than the attainment or enjoyment of the last end. Now the last end is called happiness. If therefore the happiness of man is considered in its cause or object, in that way it is something uncreated; but if it is considered in essence, in that way happiness is a created thing.

§ 2. Happiness is said to be the sovereign good of man, because it is the attainment or enjoyment of the sovereign good.

Article II.—Is happiness an activity?

R. So far as the happiness of man is something created, existing in the man himself, we must say that the happiness of man is an act. For happiness is the last perfection of man. But everything is perfect so far as it is in act; for potentiality without actuality is imperfect. Happiness therefore must consist in the last and crowning act of man. But it is manifest that activity is the last and crowning act of an active being: whence also it is called by the Philosopher “the second act.” And hence it is that each thing is said to be for the sake of its activity. It needs must be therefore that the happiness of man is a certain activity.

§ 1. Life has two meanings. One way it means the very being of the living, and in that way happiness is not life; for of God alone can it be said that His own being is His happiness. In another way life is taken to mean the activity on the part of the living thing by which activity the principle of life is reduced to act. Thus we speak of an active or contemplative life, or of a life of pleasure; and in this way the last end is called life everlasting, as is clear from the text: “This is life everlasting, that they know Thee, the only true God.”

§ 2. By the definition of Boethius, that happiness is “a state made perfect by the aggregate sum of all things good,” nothing else is meant than that the happy man is in a state of perfect good. But Aristotle has expressed the proper essence of happiness, showing by what it is that man is constituted in such a state, namely, by a certain activity.

§ 3. Action is twofold. There is one variety that proceeds from the agent to exterior matter, as the action of cutting and burning, and such an activity cannot be happiness, for such activity is not an act and perfection of the agent, but rather of the patient. There is another action immanent, or remaining in the agent himself, as feeling, understanding, and willing. Such action is a perfection and act of the agent, and an activity of this sort possibly may be happiness.

§ 4. Since happiness means some manner of final perfection, happiness must have different meanings according to the different grades of perfection that there are attainable by different beings capable of happiness. In God is happiness by essence, because His very being is His activity, because He does not enjoy any other thing than Himself. In the angels final perfection is by way of a certain activity, whereby they are united to the Uncreated Good; and this activity is in them one and everlasting. In men, in the state of the present life, final perfection is by way of an activity whereby they are united to God. But this activity cannot be everlasting or continuous,  and by consequence it is not one, because an act is multiplied by interruption; and therefore, in this state of the present life, perfect happiness is not to be had by man. Hence the Philosopher, placing the happiness of man in this life, says that it is imperfect, and after much discussion he comes to this conclusion: “We call them happy, so far as happiness can be predicated of men.” But we have a promise from God of perfect happiness, when we shall be “like the angels in Heaven.” As regards this perfect happiness, the objection drops, because in this state of happiness the mind of man is united to God by one continuous and everlasting activity. But in the present life, so far as we fall short of the unity and continuity of such an activity, so much do we lose of the perfection of happiness. There is, however, granted us a certain participation in happiness, and the more continuous and undivided the activity can be, the more will it come up to the idea of happiness. And therefore in the active life, which is busied with many things, there is less of the essence of happiness than in the contemplative life, which is busy with the one occupation of the contemplation of truth. Though at times the contemplative man is not actually engaged in contemplation, still, because he has it ready to hand, he is always able to engage in it; moreover, the very cessation for purposes of sleep or other natural occupation is ordered in his mind towards the aforesaid act of contemplation, and therefore that act seems in a manner continual.

Article III.—Is happiness an activity of sense or of pure intellect?

R. A thing may belong to happiness in three ways, essentially, antecedently,and consequently. Essentially indeed the activity of sense cannot belong to happiness. For man’s happiness consists essentially in his conjunction with the Uncreated Good, which is his last end, an end wherewith he cannot be conjoined by any activity of sense. The like conclusion follows from the fact that man’s happiness does not consist in goods of the body, which however are the only goods that we attain by the activity of sense. But activities of sense may belong to happiness both antecedently and consequently. Antecedently, in respect of imperfect happiness, such as can be had in this life: for the activity of intellect presupposes the activity of sense. Consequently, in the perfect happiness which is looked for in Heaven, because after the resurrection, “from the happiness of the soul,” as Augustine says, “there will be a certain reaction on the body and the senses of the body to perfect them in their activities.” But even then the activity whereby the human mind is united with God will not depend on sense.

Article IV.—Supposing happiness to belong to the intellectual faculty, is it an activity of the understanding or of the will?

R. For happiness two things are requisite, one which is the essence of happiness, another which is a sort of proprium of it, namely, the delight attaching to it. I say then that as for that which is the very essence of happiness, it cannot possibly consist in an act of the will. For manifestly happiness is the gaining of the last end; but the gaining of the last end does not consist in any mere act of the will. The will reaches out both to an absent end, desiring it, and to a present end, resting in it with delight. But plainly the mere desire of an end is not the gaining of an end, but a movement in that direction. As for delight, that comes over the will from the fact of the end being present, but not conversely, i.e., a thing does not become present by the mere fact of the will delighting in it. It must therefore be by something else than the act of the will that the end itself becomes present to the will. And this manifestly appears in the case of sensible ends; for if it were possible to gain money by an act of the will, a covetous man would have made his money from the first, the instant that he wished to have it; but the fact is, at first the money is away from him, and he gets it by seizing it with his hand, or by some such means, and then he is at once delighted with the money got. So then it happens also in the case of an end of the intellectual order. For from the beginning we wish to gain this intellectual end; but we actually do gain it only by this, that it becomes present to us by an act of understanding, and then the will rests delighted in the end already gained. So therefore the essence  of happiness consists in an act of understanding. But the delight that follows upon happiness belongs to the will. So Augustine says: “Happiness is joy in truth,” joy being properly the crown and complement of happiness.

§ 1. Peace belongs to the last end of man, not as being the very essence of happiness, but because it stands in relation to happiness as well antecedently as consequently. Antecedently, inasmuch as all perturbing and impeding causes are already removed from the way of the last end: consequently, inasmuch as man, when he has gained his last end, remains at peace with his desire at rest.

§ 2. The first object of the will is not its own act, as neither is the first object of sight vision, but a visible thing. Therefore from the fact that happiness belongs to the will as its first object, it follows that it does not belong to it as being its own act.

§ 4. Love ranks above knowledge in moving, but knowledge goes before love in attaining; for nothing is loved but what is known, and therefore an end of understanding is first attained by the action of understanding, even as an end of sense is first attained by the action of sense.

§ 5. To Augustine’s words, “He is happy, who has all that he wishes, and wishes nothing amiss,” it is to be said that he who has all that he wishes, is happy by having what he wishes, and that he has by something else than an act of the will. But to wish nothing amiss is required for happiness as a certain due disposition thereto.

Article V.—Is happiness an activity of the speculative or of the practical understanding?

R. Happiness consists rather in the activity of the speculative understanding than of the practical, as is evident from three considerations. First from this, that if the happiness of man is an activity, it must be the best activity of man. Now the best activity of man is that of the best power working upon the best object: but the best power is the understanding, and the best object thereof is the Divine Good, which is not the object of the practical understanding, but of the speculative. Secondly, the same appears from this, that contemplation is especially sought after for its own sake. But the act of the practical understanding is not sought after for its own sake, but for the sake of the action, and the actions themselves are directed to some end. Hence it is manifest that the last end cannot consist in the active life that is proper to the practical understanding. Thirdly, the same appears from this, that in the contemplative life man is partaker with his betters, namely, with God and the angels, to whom he is assimilated by happiness: but in what concerns the active life other animals also after a fashion are partakers with men, albeit imperfectly. And therefore the last and perfect happiness which is expected in the world to come, must consist mainly in contemplation. But imperfect happiness, such as can be had here, consists primarily and principally in contemplation, but secondarily in the activity of the practical understanding directing human actions and passions.

§ 2. The practical understanding has a good which is outside of itself, but the speculative understanding has good within itself, to wit, the contemplation of truth; and if that good be perfect, the whole man is perfected thereby and becomes good. This good within itself the practical understanding has not, but directs a man towards it.

Article VIII.—Does man’s happiness consist in the vision of the Divine Essence?

R. The last and perfect happiness of man cannot be otherwise than in the vision of the Divine Essence. In evidence of this statement two points are to be considered: first, that man is not perfectly happy, so long as there remains anything for him to desire and seek; secondly, that the perfection of every power is determined by the nature of its object. Now the object of the intellect is the essence of a thing: hence the intellect attains to perfection so far as it knows the essence of what is before it. And therefore, when a man knows an effect, and knows that it has a cause, there is in him an outstanding natural desire of knowing the essence of the cause. If therefore a human intellect knows the essence of a created effect without knowing aught of God beyond the fact of His existence, the perfection of that intellect does not yet adequately reach the First Cause, but the intellect has an outstanding natural desire of searching into the said Cause: hence it is not yet perfectly happy.  For perfect happiness, therefore, it is necessary that the intellect shall reach as far as the very essence of the First Cause.

QUESTION IV.: OF THINGS REQUISITE FOR HAPPINESS.

Article I.—Is delight requisite for happiness?

R. In four ways one thing is requisite for another. In one way as a preamble or preparation for it, as instruction is for knowledge. In another way as perfecting the thing, as the soul is requisite for the life of the body. In a third way as cooperating from without, as friends are requisite for carrying out an enterprise. In a fourth way as a concomitant, as if we were to say that heat is requisite for fire. And in this last way delight is requisite for happiness. For delight is caused by the fact of desire resting in attained good. Hence since happiness is nothing else than the attainment of the Sovereign Good, there cannot be happiness without concomitant delight.

§ 1. To Augustine’s words, that “vision is the whole reward of faith,” it is to be said that by the very fact of reward rendered, the will of him who earns it is at rest, which is to have delight.

§ 2. He who sees God cannot want for delight.

§ 3. The delight that accompanies the activity of the understanding, does not impede, but rather strengthens that activity: for acts done with delight are done with more attention and perseverance. But an extraneous delight would impede activity by distracting the attention.

Article II.—Is vision rather than delight the main element in happiness?

R. It must needs be that vision, the activity of the understanding, is better than delight. For delight consists in a certain repose of the will: but the fact of the will’s reposing in anything is only for the goodness of that wherein it reposes. If therefore the will reposes in any activity, it is from the goodness of the activity that the repose of the will proceeds. Nor does the will seek good for the sake of repose; for at that rate the end of the will would be its own act, which is against former conclusions. But the reason why the will seeks to repose in an activity, is because such an activity is the will’s own proper good. Hence it is manifest that the activity itself in which the will reposes, is more of a principal good than the repose which the will finds therein.

§ 1. As the Philosopher says, “Delight perfects activity as beauty does youth,” which beauty is consequent upon youth. Hence delight is a perfection  concomitant upon vision, not a perfection that makes vision to be perfect in its kind.

§ 2. The apprehension of sense does not attain to the general notion of good, but to some particular good which affords delight. And therefore according to the procedure of the sensitive appetite, which is in animals, activities are sought for the sake of delight. But the intellect grasps the universal idea of good, upon the attainment of which there follows delight: hence the intellect intends good pre-eminently above delight. Hence also it is that the Divine Intellect, which has the ordering of nature, has appended delights to activities for the sake of the activity. Our estimates of things must not be made simply by the ruling of the sensitive appetite, but rather by the ruling of the intellectual appetite.

Article IV.—Is rectitude of will requisite for happiness?

R. Rectitude of will is requisite for happiness both antecedently and concomitantly. Antecedently, because rectitude of will is an attitude of due regard to the last end. As matter cannot take its form unless it be duly disposed unto the same, so nothing gains its end unless it be in due regard to it. And therefore none can arrive at happiness unless he have rectitude of will. Again concomitantly, because happiness ultimately consists in the vision of the Divine Essence, which is the very essence of goodness; and thus whatever the will of him who sees the Essence of God loves, it necessarily loves it in subordination to God, as whatever the will of him who does not see the Essence of God loves, it loves it necessarily under the common idea of good which it knows; and this subordination it is that keeps the will right. Hence it is manifest that happiness cannot be without a right will.

Article VI.—Is any perfection of the body requisite for happiness?

R. If we speak of human happiness such as can be had in this life, it is manifest that a good habit of body is requisite thereto of necessity; and that by ill-health of body man may be impeded in every virtuous activity. But speaking of perfect happiness, some have laid it down that no disposition of body is requisite for happiness: nay, that it is requisite thereto for the soul to be altogether separated from the body. Augustine quotes some words of Porphyry to this effect: “That the soul may be happy, everything corporeal must be avoided.” But this is unreasonable: for as it is natural to the soul to be united to a body, it cannot be that the perfection of the soul excludes this its natural perfection. And therefore we must say that for happiness in every way perfect there is requisite a perfect disposition of body, as well antecedently as consequently. Antecedently, because as Augustine says, “If the body be such that the conduct of it becomes a difficult and burdensome task, as in the case of the flesh that is corrupted and weighs down the spirit, the mind is turned away from the vision of the highest heaven;” hence he concludes that “when this body shall be no longer animal but  spiritual, then man shall be equal to the angels, and what was his load shall be his glory.” Consequently, because from the happiness of the soul there shall be an overflow on to the body, that the body too may attain its proper perfection. Hence Augustine says: “God has made the soul of so potent a nature, that out of its full and abounding happiness there overflows upon the lower nature the freshness of incorruption.”

§ 1. Bodily good, though not the object of happiness, may yet be some ornament or complement of happiness.

§ 3. For the perfect activity of the understanding there is requisite indeed a withdrawal from this corruptible body, which weighs down the soul, but not from the spiritual body, which will be wholly subject to the spirit.

Article VII.—Are any exterior goods requisite for happiness?

R. For imperfect happiness, such as can be had in this life, exterior goods are requisite, not as being of the essence of happiness, but as instrumental to happiness: for man needs in this life the necessaries of the body for the exercise as well of contemplative as of active virtue. But for perfect happiness, which consists in the vision of God, such goods are nowise requisite. The reason is this, that whereas all such exterior goods are either requisite for the support of the animal body, or requisite for certain activities which we exercise through the animal body, perfect happiness in the vision of God  will either be in the soul without the body, or will be in a soul united to a body no longer animal but spiritual; and therefore in no way are exterior goods requisite for that happiness, bearing as they do upon animal life.

§ 2. Exterior goods, subservient as they are to animal life, are not proper to the spiritual life in which the happiness of man consists. And yet there shall be in that happiness an assemblage of all things good; because whatever good is found in those exterior things will be all possessed in the supreme source and fountain of goodness.

Article VIII.—Is the company of friends requisite for happiness?

R. If we speak of the happiness of the present life, to be happy, man needs friends, both in the active and in the contemplative life. But if we speak of the perfect happiness that will be in our heavenly country, the company of friends is not a necessary requisite of happiness: because man has all the fulness of his perfection in God. But the company of friends makes for the well-being of happiness. Hence Augustine says: “The only aid to happiness in spiritual creatures is intrinsic from the eternity, truth, and charity of the Creator: but if they are to be said to receive any extrinsic aid at all, perhaps it is in this alone, that they see one another and enjoy one another’s company.”

§ 3. The perfection of charity is essential to happiness as regards the love of God, not as regards the love of our neighbour. Hence, if there were  only one soul enjoying God, it would be happy, without having any neighbour to love. But supposing the existence of a neighbour, the love of that neighbour follows from the perfect love of God. Hence friendship is a sort of concomitant of perfect happiness.

QUESTION V.: OF THE ATTAINMENT OF HAPPINESS.

Article I.—Can man attain to happiness?

R. Whoever is capable of perfect good, can attain to happiness. That man is capable of perfect good, appears from the fact of his intellect being able to grasp universal and perfect good, and his will to desire it; and therefore man can attain to happiness.

§ 1. The way that the rational nature exceeds the sensitive is not like the way that the intellectual nature exceeds the rational. For the rational nature exceeds the sensitive in point of the object of its knowledge, because sense can nowise be cognisant of the universal, whereof reason is cognisant. But the intellectual nature exceeds the rational in point of the manner of knowing an intelligible truth. For the intellectual nature immediately apprehends the truth, whereunto the rational nature arrives by the inquiry of reason; and therefore what intellect apprehends, reason attains by a process of making  its way thither. Hence a rational nature can attain to happiness, which is the perfection of an intellectual nature, yet after another fashion than the angels: for the angels gained it immediately after the beginning of their creation, but men take time to arrive at it. But a sensitive nature can never reach this goal at all.

Article II.

§ 3. To none of the Blessed is there wanting any good that he can desire, since he has the Infinite Good itself, which is “the good of all good,” as Augustine says. But one of them is said to be happier than another according to different degrees of partaking of the same good. The addition of other goods to this does not increase happiness.

Article III.—Can any one be happy in this life?

“Man born of a woman, living for a short time, is filled with many miseries.”

R. Some manner of participation in happiness may be had in this life, but not perfect and true happiness, as may be seen from two considerations. First, from the general notion of happiness: for happiness, being a perfect and sufficient good, excludes all evil and satisfies all desire: but in this life all evil cannot be excluded. The present life is liable to many evils that cannot be avoided, ignorance on the part of the intellect, inordinate affection on the part of the desire, and manifold penal inflictions on the part of the body. In like  manner also the desire of good cannot be satisfied in this life. For naturally man desires permanence in the good that he has. But the goods of this life are transient, as life itself is transient, which we naturally desire, and would wish permanently to hold, since every man naturally shrinks from death. Secondly, if we consider that wherein particularly happiness consists, to wit, the vision of the Divine Essence, that cannot be the portion of man in this life.

Article IV.—Can happiness once attained be ever lost?

R.