Anthropology
AnthropologyCHAPTER ICHAPTER IICHAPTER IIICHAPTER IVCHAPTER VCHAPTER VICHAPTER VIICHAPTER VIIICHAPTER IXCHAPTER XCopyright
Anthropology
R. R. Marett
CHAPTER I
SCOPE OF ANTHROPOLOGYIn this chapter I propose to say something, firstly, about
the ideal scope of anthropology; secondly, about its ideal
limitations; and, thirdly and lastly, about its actual relations to
existing studies. In other words, I shall examine the extent of its
claim, and then go on to examine how that claim, under modern
conditions of science and education, is to be made
good.Firstly, then, what is the ideal scope of anthropology? Taken
at its fullest and best, what ought it to comprise?Anthropology is the whole history of man as fired and
pervaded by the idea of evolution. Man in evolution—that is the
subject in its full reach. Anthropology studies man as he occurs at
all known times. It studies him as he occurs in all known parts of
the world. It studies him body and soul together—as a bodily
organism, subject to conditions operating in time and space, which
bodily organism is in intimate relation with a soul-life, also
subject to those same conditions. Having an eye to such conditions
from first to last, it seeks to plot out the general series of the
changes, bodily and mental together, undergone by man in the course
of his history. Its business is simply to describe. But, without
exceeding the limits of its scope, it can and must proceed from the
particular to the general; aiming at nothing less than a
descriptive formula that shall sum up the whole series of changes
in which the evolution of man consists.That will do, perhaps, as a short account of the ideal scope
of anthropology. Being short, it is bound to be rather formal and
colourless. To put some body into it, however, it is necessary to
breathe but a single word. That word is: Darwin.Anthropology is the child of Darwin. Darwinism makes it
possible. Reject the Darwinian point of view, and you must reject
anthropology also. What, then, is Darwinism? Not a cut-and-dried
doctrine. Not a dogma. Darwinism is a working hypothesis. You
suppose something to be true, and work away to see whether, in the
light of that supposed truth, certain facts fit together better
than they do on any other supposition. What is the truth that
Darwinism supposes? Simply that all the forms of life in the world
are related together; and that the relations manifested in time and
space between the different lives are sufficiently uniform to be
described under a general formula, or law of
evolution.This means that man must, for certain purposes of science,
toe the line with the rest of living things. And at first,
naturally enough, man did not like it. He was too lordly. For a
long time, therefore, he pretended to be fighting for the Bible,
when he was really fighting for his own dignity. This was rather
hard on the Bible, which has nothing to do with the Aristotelian
theory of the fixity of species; though it might seem possible to
read back something of the kind into the primitive creation-stories
preserved in Genesis. Now-a-days, however, we have mostly got over
the first shock to our family pride. We are all Darwinians in a
passive kind of way. But we need to darwinize actively. In the
sciences that have to do with plants, and with the rest of the
animals besides man, naturalists have been so active in their
darwinizing that the pre-Darwinian stuff is once for all laid by on
the shelf. When man, however, engages on the subject of his noble
self, the tendency still is to say: We accept Darwinism so long as
it is not allowed to count, so long as we may go on believing the
same old stuff in the same old way.How do we anthropologists propose to combat this tendency? By
working away at our subject, and persuading people to have a look
at our results. Once people take up anthropology, they may be
trusted not to drop it again. It is like learning to sleep with
your window open. What could be more stupefying than to shut
yourself up in a closet and swallow your own gas? But is it any
less stupefying to shut yourself up within the last few thousand
years of the history of your own corner of the world, and suck in
the stale atmosphere of its own self-generated prejudices? Or, to
vary the metaphor, anthropology is like travel. Every one starts by
thinking that there is nothing so perfect as his own parish. But
let a man go aboard ship to visit foreign parts, and, when he
returns home, he will cause that parish to wake up.With Darwin, then, we anthropologists say: Let any and every
portion of human history be studied in the light of the whole
history of mankind, and against the background of the history of
living things in general. It is the Darwinian outlook that matters.
None of Darwin's particular doctrines will necessarily endure the
test of time and trial. Into the melting-pot must they go as often
as any man of science deems it fitting. But Darwinism as the touch
of nature that makes the whole world kin can hardly pass away. At
any rate, anthropology stands or falls with the working hypothesis,
derived from Darwinism, of a fundamental kinship and continuity
amid change between all the forms of human life.It remains to add that, hitherto, anthropology has devoted
most of its attention to the peoples of rude—that is to say, of
simple—culture, who are vulgarly known to us as "savages." The main
reason for this, I suppose, is that nobody much minds so long as
the darwinizing kind of history confines itself to outsiders. Only
when it is applied to self and friends is it resented as an
impertinence. But, although it has always up to now pursued the
line of least resistance, anthropology does not abate one jot or
tittle of its claim to be the whole science, in the sense of the
whole history, of man. As regards the word, call it science, or
history, or anthropology, or anything else—what does it matter? As
regards the thing, however, there can be no compromise. We
anthropologists are out to secure this: that there shall not be one
kind of history for savages and another kind for ourselves, but the
same kind of history, with the same evolutionary principle running
right through it, for all men, civilized and savage, present and
past.So much for the ideal scope of anthropology. Now, in the
second place, for its ideal limitations. Here, I am afraid, we must
touch for a moment on very deep and difficult questions. But it is
well worth while to try at all costs to get firm hold of the fact
that anthropology, though a big thing, is not
everything.It will be enough to insist briefly on the following points:
that anthropology is science in whatever way history is science;
that it is not philosophy, though it must conform to its needs; and
that it is not policy, though it may subserve its
designs.Anthropology is science in the sense of specialized research
that aims at truth for truth's sake. Knowing by parts is science,
knowing the whole as a whole is philosophy. Each supports the
other, and there is no profit in asking which of the two should
come first. One is aware of the universe as the whole universe,
however much one may be resolved to study its details one at a
time. The scientific mood, however, is uppermost when one says:
Here is a particular lot of things that seem to hang together in a
particular way; let us try to get a general idea of what that way
is. Anthropology, then, specializes on the particular group of
human beings, which itself is part of the larger particular group
of living beings. Inasmuch as it takes over the evolutionary
principle from the science dealing with the larger group, namely
biology, anthropology may be regarded as a branch of biology. Let
it be added, however, that, of all the branches of biology, it is
the one that is likely to bring us nearest to the true meaning of
life; because the life of human beings must always be nearer to
human students of life than, say, the life of plants.But, you will perhaps object, anthropology was previously
identified with history, and now it is identified with science,
namely, with a branch of biology? Is history science? The answer
is, Yes. I know that a great many people who call themselves
historians say that it is not, apparently on the ground that, when
it comes to writing history, truth for truth's sake is apt to bring
out the wrong results. Well, the doctored sort of history is not
science, nor anthropology, I am ready to admit. But now let us
listen to another and a more serious objection to the claim of
history to be science. Science, it will be said by many earnest men
of science, aims at discovering laws that are clean out of time.
History, on the other hand, aims at no more than the generalized
description of one or another phase of a time-process. To this it
may be replied that physics, and physics only, answers to this
altogether too narrow conception of science. The laws of matter in
motion are, or seem to be, of the timeless or mathematical kind.
Directly we pass on to biology, however, laws of this kind are not
to be discovered, or at any rate are not discovered. Biology deals
with life, or, if you like, with matter as living. Matter moves.
Life evolves. We have entered a new dimension of existence. The
laws of matter in motion are not abrogated, for the simple reason
that in physics one makes abstraction of life, or in other words
leaves its peculiar effects entirely out of account. But they are
transcended. They are multiplied byx, an unknown quantity. This being so from the standpoint of
pure physics, biology takes up the tale afresh, and devises means
of its own for describing the particular ways in which things hang
together in virtue of their being alive. And biology finds that it
cannot conveniently abstract away the reference to time. It cannot
treat living things as machines. What does it do, then? It takes
the form of history. It states that certain things have changed in
certain ways, and goes on to show, so far as it can, that the
changes are on the whole in a certain direction. In short, it
formulates tendencies, and these are its only laws. Some
tendencies, of course, appear to be more enduring than others, and
thus may be thought to approximate more closely to laws of the
timeless kind. Butx, the
unknown quantity, the something or other that is not physical, runs
through them all, however much or little they may seem to endure.
For science, at any rate, which departmentalizes the world, and
studies it bit by bit, there is no getting over the fact that
living beings in general, and human beings in particular, are
subject to an evolution which is simple matter of
history.And now what about philosophy? I am not going into
philosophical questions here. For that reason I am not going to
describe biology as natural history, or anthropology as the natural
history of man. Let philosophers discuss what "nature" is going to
mean for them. In science the word is question-begging; and the
only sound rule in science is to beg as few philosophical questions
as you possibly can. Everything in the world is natural, of course,
in the sense that things are somehow all akin—all of a piece. We
are simply bound to take in the parts as parts of a whole, and it
is just this fact that makes philosophy not only possible but
inevitable. All the same, this fact does not prevent the parts from
having their own specific natures and specific ways of behaving.
The people who identify the natural with the physical are putting
all their money on one specific kind of nature or behaviour that is
to be found in the world. In the case of man they are backing the
wrong horse. The horse to back is the horse that goes. As a going
concern, however, anthropology, as part of evolutionary biology, is
a history of vital tendencies which are not natural in the sense of
merely physical.What are the functions of philosophy as contrasted with
science? Two. Firstly, it must be critical. It must police the city
of the sciences, preventing them from interfering with each other's
rights and free development. Co-operation by all means, as, for
instance, between anthropology and biology. But no jumping other
folks' claims and laying down the law for all; as, for instance,
when physics would impose the kind of method applicable to machines
on the sciences of evolving life. Secondly, philosophy must be
synthetic. It must put all the ways of knowing together, and
likewise put these in their entirety together with all the ways of
feeling and acting; so that there may result a theory of reality
and of the good life, in that organic interdependence of the two
which our very effort to put things together presupposes as its
object.What, then, are to be the relations between anthropology and
philosophy? On the one hand, the question whether anthropology can
help philosophy need not concern us here. That is for the
philosopher to determine. On the other hand, philosophy can help
anthropology in two ways: in its critical capacity, by helping it
to guard its own claim, and develop freely without interference
from outsiders; and in its synthetic capacity, perhaps, by
suggesting the rule that, of two types of explanation, for
instance, the physical and the biological, the more abstract is
likely to be farther away from the whole truth, whereas,
contrariwise, the more you take in, the better your chance of
really understanding.It remains to speak about policy. I use this term to mean any
and all practical exploitation of the results of science.
Sometimes, indeed, it is hard to say where science ends and policy
begins, as we saw in the case of those gentlemen who would doctor
their history, because practically it pays to have a good conceit
of ourselves, and believe that our side always wins its battles.
Anthropology, however, would borrow something besides the
evolutionary principle from biology, namely, its disinterestedness.
It is not hard to be candid about bees and ants; unless, indeed,
one is making a parable of them. But as anthropologists we must
try, what is so much harder, to be candid about ourselves. Let us
look at ourselves as if we were so many bees and ants, not
forgetting, of course, to make use of the inside information that
in the case of the insects we so conspicuously lack.This does not mean that human history, once constructed
according to truth-regarding principles, should and could not be
used for the practical advantage of mankind. The anthropologist,
however, is not, as such, concerned with the practical employment
to which his discoveries are put. At most, he may, on the strength
of a conviction that truth is mighty and will prevail for human
good, invite practical men to study his facts and generalizations
in the hope that, by knowing mankind better, they may come to
appreciate and serve it better. For instance, the administrator,
who rules over savages, is almost invariably quite well-meaning,
but not seldom utterly ignorant of native customs and beliefs. So,
in many cases, is the missionary, another type of person in
authority, whose intentions are of the best, but whose methods too
often leave much to be desired. No amount of zeal will suffice,
apart from scientific insight into the conditions of the practical
problem. And the education is to be got by paying for it. But
governments and churches, with some honourable exceptions, are
still wofully disinclined to provide their probationers with the
necessary special training; though it is ignorance that always
proves most costly in the long run. Policy, however, including bad
policy, does not come within the official cognizance of the
anthropologist. Yet it is legitimate for him to hope that, just as
for many years already physiological science has indirectly
subserved the art of medicine, so anthropological science may
indirectly, though none the less effectively, subserve an art of
political and religious healing in the days to come.The third and last part of this chapter will show how, under
modern conditions of science and education, anthropology is to
realize its programme. Hitherto, the trouble with anthropologists
has been to see the wood for the trees. Even whilst attending
mainly to the peoples of rude culture, they have heaped together
facts enough to bewilder both themselves and their readers. The
time has come to do some sorting; or rather the sorting is doing
itself. All manner of groups of special students, interested in
some particular side of human history, come now-a-days to the
anthropologist, asking leave to borrow from his stock of facts the
kind that they happen to want. Thus he, as general storekeeper, is
beginning to acquire, almost unconsciously, a sense of order
corresponding to the demands that are made upon him. The goods that
he will need to hand out in separate batches are being gradually
arranged by him on separate shelves. Our best way, then, of
proceeding with the present inquiry, is to take note of these
shelves. In other words, we must consider one by one the special
studies that claim to have a finger in the anthropological
pie.Or, to avoid the disheartening task of reviewing an array of
bloodless "-ologies," let us put the question to ourselves thus: Be
it supposed that a young man or woman who wants to take a course,
of at least a year's length, in the elements of anthropology, joins
some university which is thoroughly in touch with the scientific
activities of the day. A university, as its very name implies,
ought to be an all-embracing assemblage of higher studies, so
adjusted to each other that, in combination, they provide beginners
with a good general education; whilst, severally, they offer to
more advanced students the opportunity of doing this or that kind
of specific research. In such a well-organized university, then,
how would our budding anthropologist proceed to form a preliminary
acquaintance with the four corners of his subject? What departments
must he attend in turn? Let us draw him up a curriculum, praying
meanwhile that the multiplicity of the demands made upon him will
not take away his breath altogether. Man is a many-sided being; so
there is no help for it if anthropology also is
many-sided.For one thing, he must sit at the feet of those whose
particular concern is with pre-historic man. It is well to begin
here, since thus will the glamour of the subject sink into his soul
at the start. Let him, for instance, travel back in thought to the
Europe of many thousands of years ago, shivering under the effects
of the great ice-age, yet populous with human beings so far like
ourselves that they were alive to the advantage of a good fire,
made handy tools out of stone and wood and bone, painted animals on
the walls of their caves, or engraved them on mammoth-ivory, far
more skilfully than most of us could do now, and buried their dead
in a ceremonial way that points to a belief in a future life. Thus,
too, he will learn betimes how to blend the methods and materials
of different branches of science. A human skull, let us say, and
some bones of extinct animals, and some chipped flints are all
discovered side by side some twenty feet below the level of the
soil. At least four separate authorities must be called in before
the parts of the puzzle can be fitted together.Again, he must be taught something about race, or inherited
breed, as it applies to man. A dose of practical anatomy—that is to
say, some actual handling and measuring of the principal portions
of the human frame in its leading varieties—will enable our
beginner to appreciate the differences of outer form that
distinguish, say, the British colonist in Australia from the native
"black-fellow," or the whites from the negroes, and redskins, and
yellow Asiatics in the United States. At this point, he may
profitably embark on the details of the Darwinian hypothesis of the
descent of man. Let him search amongst the manifold modern versions
of the theory of human evolution for the one that comes nearest to
explaining the degrees of physical likeness and unlikeness shown by
men in general as compared with the animals, especially the
man-like apes; and again, those shown by the men of divers ages and
regions as compared with each other. Nor is it enough for him, when
thus engaged, to take note simply of physical features—the shape of
the skull, the colour of the skin, the tint and texture of the
hair, and so on. There are likewise mental characters that seem to
be bound up closely with the organism and to follow the breed. Such
are the so-called instincts, the study of which should be helped
out by excursions into the mind-history of animals, of children,
and of the insane. Moreover, the measuring and testing of mental
functions, and, in particular, of the senses, is now-a-days carried
on by means of all sorts of ingenious instruments; and some
experience of their use will be all to the good, when problems of
descent are being tackled.Further, our student must submit to a thorough grounding in
world-geography with its physical and human sides welded firmly
together. He must be able to pick out on the map the headquarters
of all the more notable peoples, not merely as they are now, but
also as they were at various outstanding moments of the past. His
next business is to master the main facts about the natural
conditions to which each people is subjected—the climate, the
conformation of land and sea, the animals and plants. From here it
is but a step to the economic life—the food-supply, the clothing,
the dwelling-places, the principal occupations, the implements of
labour. A selected list of books of travel must be consulted. No
less important is it to work steadily through the show-cases of a
good ethnological museum. Nor will it suffice to have surveyed the
world by regions. The communications between regions—the migrations
and conquests, the trading and the borrowing of customs—must be
traced and accounted for. Finally, on the basis of their
distribution, which the learner must chart out for himself on blank
maps of the world, the chief varieties of the useful arts and
appliances of man can be followed from stage to stage of their
development.Of the special studies concerned with man the next in order
might seem to be that which deals with the various forms of human
society; since, in a sense, social organization must depend
directly on material circumstances. In another and perhaps a deeper
sense, however, the prime condition of true sociality is something
else, namely, the exclusively human gift of articulate speech. To
what extent, then, must our novice pay attention to the history of
language? Speculation about its far-off origins is now-a-days
rather out of fashion. Moreover, language is no longer supposed to
provide, by itself at any rate, and apart from other clues, a key
to the endless riddles of racial descent. What is most needed,
then, is rather some elementary instruction concerning the organic
connection between language and thought, and concerning their joint
development as viewed against the background of the general
development of society. And, just as words and thoughts are
essentially symbols, so there are also gesture-symbols and written
symbols, whilst again another set of symbols is in use for
counting. All these pre-requisites of human intercourse may be
conveniently taken together.Coming now to the analysis of the forms of society, the
beginner must first of all face the problem: "What makes a people
one?" Neither blood, nor territory, nor language, but only the fact
of being more or less compactly organized in a political society,
will be found to yield the unifying principle required. Once the
primary constitution of the body politic has been made out, a limit
is set up, inside of which a number of fairly definite forms of
grouping offer themselves for examination; whilst outside of it
various social relationships of a vaguer kind have also to be
considered. Thus, amongst institutions of the internal kind, the
family by itself presents a wide field of research; though in
certain cases it is liable to be overshadowed by some other sort of
organization, such as, notably, the clan. Under the same rubric
fall the many forms of more or less voluntary association,
economic, religious, and so forth. On the other hand, outside the
circle of the body politic there are, at all known stages of
society, mutual understandings that regulate war, trade, travel,
the celebration of common rites, the interchange of ideas. Here,
then, is an abundance of types of human association, to be first
scrutinized separately, and afterwards considered in relation to
each other.Closely connected with the previous subject is the history of
law. Every type of association, in a way, has its law, whereby its
members are constrained to fulfil a certain set of obligations.
Thus our student will pass on straight from the forms of society to
the most essential of their functions. The fact that, amongst the
less civilized peoples, the law is uncodified and merely customary,
whilst the machinery for enforcing it is, though generally
effective enough, yet often highly indefinite and occasional, makes
the tracing of the growth of legal institutions from their
rudiments no less vitally important, though it makes it none the
easier. The history of authority is a strictly kindred topic.
Legislating and judging on the one hand, and governing on the
other, are different aspects of the same general function. In
accordance, then, with the order already indicated, law and
government as administered by the political society in the person
of its representatives, chiefs, elders, war-lords, priest-kings,
and so forth, must first be examined; then the jurisdiction and
discipline of subordinate bodies, such as the family and the clan,
or again the religious societies, trade guilds, and the rest; then,
lastly, the international conventions, with the available means of
ensuring their observance.Again, the history of religion is an allied theme of
far-reaching interest. For the understanding of the ruder forms of
society it may even be said to furnish the master-key. At this
stage, religion is the mainstay of law and government. The
constraining force of custom makes itself felt largely through a
magnifying haze of mystic sanctions; whilst, again, the position of
a leader of society rests for the most part on the supernormal
powers imputed to him. Religion and magic, then, must be carefully
studied if we would understand how the various persons and bodies
that exercise authority are assisted, or else hindered, in their
efforts to maintain social discipline. Apart from this fundamental
inquiry, there is another, no less important in its way, to which
the study of religion and magic opens up a path. This is the
problem how reflection manages as it were to double human
experience, by setting up beside the outer world of sense an inner
world of thought-relations. Now constructive imagination is the
queen of those mental functions which meet in what we loosely term
"thought"; and imagination is ever most active where, on the outer
fringe of the mind's routine work, our inarticulate questionings
radiate into the unknown. When the genius has his vision, almost
invariably, among the ruder peoples, it is accepted by himself and
his society as something supernormal and sacred, whether its fruit
be an act of leadership or an edict, a practical invention or a
work of art, a story of the past or a prophecy, a cure or a
devastating curse. Moreover, social tradition treasures the memory
of these revelations, and, blending them with the contributions of
humbler folk—for all of us dream our dreams—provides in myth and
legend and tale, as well as in manifold other art-forms, a stimulus
to the inspiration of future generations. For most purposes fine
art, at any rate during its more rudimentary stages, may be studied
in connection with religion.So far as law and religion will not account for the varieties
of social behaviour, the novice may most conveniently consider them
under the head of morals. The forms of social intercourse, the
fashions, the festivities, are imposed on us by our fellows from
without, and none the less effectively because as a general rule we
fall in with them as a matter of course. The difference between
manners and morals of the higher order is due simply to the more
pressing need, in the case of our most serious duties, of a
reflective sanction, a "moral sense," to break us in to the common
service. It is no easy task to keep legal and religious penalties
or rewards out of the reckoning, when trying to frame an estimate
of what the notions of right and wrong, prevalent in a given
society, amount to in themselves; nevertheless, it is worth doing,
and valuable collections of material exist to aid the work. The
facts about education, which even amongst rude peoples is often
carried on far into manhood, throw much light on this problem. So
do the moralizings embodied the traditional lore of the folk—the
proverbs, the beast-fables, the stories of heroes.There remains the individual to be studied in himself. If the
individual be ignored by social science, as would sometimes appear
to be the case, so much the worse for social science, which, to a
corresponding extent, falls short of being truly anthropological.
Throughout the history of man, our beginner should be on the
look-out for the signs, and the effects, of personal initiative.
Freedom of choice, of course, is limited by what there is to choose
from; so that the development of what may be termed social
opportunity should be concurrently reviewed. Again, it is the aim
of every moral system so to educate each man that his directive
self may be as far as possible identified with his social self.
Even suicide is not a man's own affair, according to the voice of
society which speaks in the moral code. Nevertheless, lest the
important truth be overlooked that social control implies a will
that must meet the control half-way, it is well for the student of
man to pay separate and special attention to the individual agent.
The last word in anthropology is: Know thyself.
CHAPTER II
ANTIQUITY OF MAN
History, in the narrower sense of the word, depends on
written records. As we follow back history to the point at which
our written records grow hazy, and the immediate ancestors or
predecessors of the peoples who appear in history are disclosed in
legend that needs much eking out by the help of the spade, we pass
into proto-history. At the back of that, again, beyond the point at
which written records are of any avail at all, comes
pre-history.
How, then, you may well inquire, does the pre-historian get
to work? What is his method of linking facts together? And what are
the sources of his information?