Erhalten Sie Zugang zu diesem und mehr als 300000 Büchern ab EUR 5,99 monatlich.
What makes philosophy on the continent of Europe so different and exciting? And why does it have such a reputation for being 'difficult'? Continental philosophy was initiated amid the revolutionary ferment of the 18th century, philosophers such as Kant and Hegel confronting the extremism of the time with theories that challenged the very formation of individual and social consciousness. Covering the great philosophers of the modern and postmodern eras – from Nietzsche, Heidegger, Derrida and Deleuze right to up Agamben and ?i?ek – and philosophical movements from German idealism to deconstruction and feminism – Christopher Kul-Want and Piero brilliantly elucidate some of the most thrilling and powerful ideas ever to have been discussed.
Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:
Seitenzahl: 107
Veröffentlichungsjahr: 2014
Das E-Book (TTS) können Sie hören im Abo „Legimi Premium” in Legimi-Apps auf:
Published by Icon Books Ltd, Omnibus Business Centre, 39–41 North Road, London N7 9DP email: [email protected]
ISBN: 978-184831-775-8
Text copyright © 2013 Christopher Kui-Want Illustrations copyright © 2013 Icon Books Ltd
The author has asserted his moral rights.
Edited by Duncan Heath
No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, or by any means, without prior permission in writing from the publisher.
Contents
Cover
Title Page
Copyright
Thinking creatively
What is Continental philosophy?
A distinguished company
Continental vs. Analytic philosophy
The value of logic
A shared history
Against repression
The limitations of theory
Into the unknown
Experience and the Self
The search for structure
Suspicion of universal truths
The fantasy of consciousness
The symbolic order
The Trojan horse of communication
The unconscious: a blind spot
The universal medium of exchange
“Incalculable relations”
“They do not know it, but they are doing it”
Kant and the unknowable
Kant’s Copernican revolution
The power of the new
Alterity: the Other
The sublime
Nietzsche’s verdict: God is dead
The death of metaphysics?
Metaphysics and language
A question of perspective
The spectre of nihilism
Absurd metaphysics
Kant withdraws
Metaphysics by the back door
The colonial “Other”
Re-thinking the unknown
The will to power
Love thy neighbour?
The birth of the Overman
Heidegger: the end of modernity?
The threat of technology
Hegel: history’s perfect conclusion
Masters and slaves
Being and Time
The problem with modernity
Dasein
The limits of understanding
Art as a sign of the end
The puzzle of Communism’s failure
The Frankfurt School
Consumption as desire
Oppositional art
Walter Benjamin and “high Capitalism”
Violence and the law
Striking against Capitalist logic
The power of montage
Alienation visible
The storm of progress
Further influence of Nietzsche
A philosophy of expenditure
The plenitude of excess
Fiction and reality in psychoanalysis
“I myself do not exist …
Sartre: Existentialism and authenticity
Nausea: the chaos behind language
Freedom of choice
Fighting terror with commitment
Existentialism and Marxism
1968: the watershed
Refusing fixed meaning
Collapse of the ideologies
Evental occurrences
The “trace” of Communism
Lyotard: the question of knowledge
Information overload
The limits of the mind
Rancière and the unheard voice
Derrida: the metaphysics of presence
Saussure’s limitless meanings
Deconstruction
Derrida the juggler
“Peut-être”
Thinking about friendship
Back to Nietzsche
Phallo-logocentrism
Woman cannot lack
Jouissance
A void in representation
The subject as producer
The private and the political
Producing producers
Biopolitics: multiple forces of power
Monitoring for normality
The terrorist state
Separating violence and the law
The power of language
“As if not”
Neither in heaven nor in hell
“I would prefer not to”
The black hole of the bourgeoisie
The alterity of death
Language at degree zero
Deleuze: “schizoanalysis”
Anti-Oedipus
The Metamorphosis: schizophrenic desire
The body without organs
Pure immanence
Casting off the shackles
Glossary
Further Reading
About the Author
Acknowledgements
About the Illustrator
Index
As the great Continental philosopher Friedrich Nietzsche asserted, we only begin to think and live creatively when we no longer expect the world to answer and mirror our assumptions about ourselves. Otherwise we are likely to become dull and complacent:
HAIL, CONTINUAL PLODDERS, HAIL! LENGTHEN OUT THE TEDIOUS TALE, PEDANT, STILL IN HEAD AND KNEE, DULL, OF HUMOUR NOT A TRACE PERMANENTLY COMMONPLACE, SANS GéNIE ET SANS ESPRIT! (‘LACKING CREATIVITY AND NO WIT!’)
“Continental philosophy” is a name for the desire to exist beyond the kind of comfortable self-delusion that Nietzsche satirizes. If we remain relatively stable and unchanging in terms of our thinking, then the very power of life for change and creation will become exhausted.
WHAT WILL RESULT IS A MERE REPETITION OF THE SAME MONOTONOUS THING, A KIND OF LIVING DEATH.
Continental philosophy is based on the intuition that thinking can oppose inertia and the intractable wish to stay the same.
“Continental philosophy” refers to a radical form of philosophy developed by European thinkers writing in the period from the 18th-century Enlightenment to the present day. The major thinkers in Continental philosophy originated from Germany and northern Europe, but by the mid-20th century this type of thinking had largely shifted to France. As Alain Badiou, one of France’s leading contemporary philosophers, observes:
ALL OF FRENCH PHILOSOPHY IS, IN REALITY, A DISCUSSION OF THE GERMAN HERITAGE WITH ITS FORMATIVE MOMENTS IN THE 1930S AND 1940S. Alain Badiou
The close connection between French 20th-century philosophy and earlier German thought is shown by the fact that nearly every major French philosopher of this period has published books on the great German philosophers Kant, Hegel, Nietzsche and Heidegger.
The incredibly fertile seam of thinking that Continental philosophy represents is indicated by a roll call of its major philosophers.
FROM GERMANY AND NORTHERN EUROPE THIS INCLUDES: THE MOST SIGNIFICANT FRENCH PHILOSOPHERS IN THE CONTINENTAL TRADITION COMPRISE:
Immanuel Kant Johann Gottlieb Fichte Friedrich Schelling Georg W.F. Hegel Arthur Schopenhauer Friedrich Nietzsche Edmund Husserl Martin Heidegger
Georges Bataille Maurice Merleau-Ponty Jean-Paul Sartre Roland Barthes Maurice Blanchot Jean-François Lyotard Michel Foucault Jacques Derrida Gilles Deleuze Luce Irigaray Jean-Luc Nancy Jacques Rancière Alain Badiou
Since contemporary French philosophy has been engaged in a long-running conversation with psychoanalysis and the Marxist* intellectual tradition, the list of Continental philosophers also embraces the psychoanalysts Sigmund Freud, Melanie Klein, Jacques Lacan and Julia Kristeva, as well as Karl Marx and the Frankfurt School of philosophy, especially Max Horkheimer, Theodor Adorno, Herbert Marcuse, Walter Benjamin and Jürgen Habermas.
Today, Continental philosophy is not exclusively French. Significant contributions have been made by Slavoj Žižek, from Slovenia, as well as Italian philosophers such as Giorgio Agamben and Gianni Vattimo.
Today it’s common to refer to two predominant types of philosophical thought: Continental philosophy and Analytic philosophy. The term “Continental philosophy” was first coined in the 1950s in Britain by university departments of Analytic philosophy as a term of criticism and even abuse. Universities in the US followed suit in the 1960s and 70s.
CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY REPRESENTS WHAT WE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHERS WISH TO REJECT.
Although the term “Continental philosophy” stems from the second half of the 20th century it was not a term that any of the philosophers, themselves, would have recognized when they were writing in the 18th, 19th and first half of the 20th centuries.
The two traditions of Analytic and Continental philosophies are often opposed to each other and there have been many disputes between the differently aligned philosophers about each other’s work. These disputes have had a significant effect on the academic agendas and staffing of university departments of philosophy over the past four decades.
ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHY CONTINUES TO PREDOMINATE IN DEPARTMENTS OF PHILOSOPHY IN THE US AND EVEN IN EUROPE.
While Continental philosophy has something of a presence in university departments of philosophy, its influence is felt more in the humanities, in the fields of literary studies, art theory and cultural studies.
Analytic philosophy traces its origins to the philosophies of Bertrand Russell (1872–1970) and Ludwig Wittgenstein (1889–1951). In the early decades of the 20th century at Cambridge University these founders of the Analytic tradition subjected the structures of reasoning in both mathematics and language to a critique of logic.
WE USED LOGIC TO TEST THE EFFECTIVENESS OF MATHEMATICS AND LANGUAGE IN TERMS OF MEANING.
Today, Analytic philosophy is a broad subject area encompassing many interdisciplinary concerns. However, in the 1950s there was the belief that Analytic philosophy represented prized values of logical rigour and clarity as a means of gaining, if not objectivity, then at least some form of impartiality. In contrast, Continental philosophy was seen, at best, as a branch of literature and poetry and, at worst, as a form of sophistry disguising its lack of rationality through an opaque and difficult language.
Both Analytic and Continental philosophy trace their origins back to German philosophy and, before that, to Descartes in the 17th century and ultimately to ancient Greek philosophy (the pre-Socratics, Plato, Aristotle et al). Given these shared histories, the perceived differences between the two approaches are not always so clear.
TODAY, THERE ARE PHILOSOPHERS SUCH AS THE AMERICANS RICHARD RORTY AND HUBERT DREYFUS WHO WORK ACROSS BOTH TRADITIONS. AND THE ANALYTIC PHILOSOPHER WITTGENSTEIN’S IDEAS ABOUT LANGUAGE AS A FORM OF GAME-PLAY WHOSE STRUCTURE IS CONSTANTLY CHANGING HAS RESONANCES FOR CONTINENTAL PHILOSOPHY.
Setting entrenched views and clichéd dichotomies aside, this book will focus on French philosophy and what it inherited from the mid-20th century onwards from its German predecessors.
The first issue that Continental philosophy wishes to tackle is that of repression, or unfreedom, as this applies both to individuals and society.
REPRESSION CAN BE DEFINED IN ITS WIDEST SENSE AS AN ADHERENCE TO FIXED VALUES AND IDEAS ABOUT HOW TO THINK AND BEHAVE AND, ULTIMATELY, EXPERIENCE LIFE … … IRRESPECTIVE OF WHETHER THIS IS ADOPTED CONSCIOUSLY OR NOT, AND WILLINGLY OR NOT.
Following this, the second issue for Continental philosophy is how to think, write about and, finally, affirm the possibility of freedom from repression – but without resorting to preconceived ideas dictating what the experience of freedom might consist of, or be like, for that would lead to further repression.
For the purpose of analysing individual and social forms of repression Continental philosophy makes use of an actively interpretative (sometimes called hermeneutic*) and historical approach that aims to understand its origins and structural operations.
THIS IS NOT NECESSARILY TO DISSOLVE THE THINKING THAT SUSTAINS REPRESSION, BUT RATHER TO OPEN IT UP TO ITS OWN CONTRADICTIONS, ELISIONS AND IDEALISTIC FANTASIES.
The first philosopher to adopt this approach was Friedrich Nietzsche (1844–1900). Using the term “genealogy” to refer to an analysis of forces of power and ideology*, Nietzsche inquired into the development of a repressive tendency in Western thinking beginning with Plato’s philosophy in the 5th century BC, followed by the introduction of Christian theology.
Insofar as Continental philosophers view repression as a continuing burden within the history of the West, they offer ways of thinking about how to overcome this condition. This involves acknowledging the role of the unconscious (hence the engagement with psychoanalysis).
WE ALSO ADMIT THAT THEORY WILL ONLY GET US SO FAR. THAT’S WHY WE HAVE A PROFOUND INTEREST IN ART, LITERATURE AND BORDERLINE PSYCHOLOGICAL STATES.
Many of the great Continental philosophers develop elaborate systems and structures of their own, but their work is also infused with a literary style that deliberately thwarts simple ideas of transparent clarity, so as to allow language its own sense of artifice, play and fluidity.
To this end many Continental philosophers develop a philosophy that embraces stories, epigrams and aphorisms (Nietzsche, Benjamin, Barthes, Derrida). Alternatively, they adopt a dense, complex language of phrasing and sentence that is often difficult and resistant in a deliberate attempt to step outside what is familiar and taken for granted (Heidegger, Adorno, Derrida, Deleuze).
TOGETHER, ALL OF THESE ASPECTS GIVE THE TEXT AN UNSTABLE CHARACTER THAT IS IRREDUCIBLE TO A SINGULAR MEANING.
Continental philosophers were by no means the first to introduce such literary strategies into their writing. The book On Nature (Phusis) by the Greek philosopher Heraclitus (535–475 BC) plays with sentence structure and is written in a series of epigrams and aphorisms that employ rhyme, assonance and puns. One of Heraclitus’ poetic epigrams is:
OVER THE SAME RIVERS, STEPPING INTO THEM DIFFERENT AND AGAIN DIFFERENT WATERS FLOW.
Another, that plays on several meanings of the Greek word bios, is: “The bow (bios): its name is life (bios), its work is death.” In both of these epigrams Heraclitus uses layered metaphors to undermine any stable sense of meaning to existence. Thus, in the first epigram the river and the person who steps into it a second time never remain the same; while in the second epigram death is the work of life.
Both Nietzsche and Heidegger admired Heraclitus. For them, Heraclitus’ ability to embrace opposites and his understanding that there are always different points of view and perspectives about “reality” struck a deep chord. Above all, however, they respected Heraclitus’ view that creativity and change are about stepping into the unknown.
IF YOU DON’T EXPECT THE UNEXPECTED YOU WON’T FIND IT OUT.
About Heraclitus Nietzsche eulogized: “In his proximity I feel altogether warmer and better than anywhere else. My doctrine might in the end have been taught already by him.” (Ecce Homo: How One Becomes What One Is, 1888)
The issue of experience – the experience of repression or, alternatively, an independence from repression – lies at the heart of Continental philosophy’s concerns. Inevitably, this raises questions about how experience may be represented and who is representing it.
IN TURN, THIS LEADS TO QUESTIONS ABOUT THE CONCEPTION OF THE