Erhalten Sie Zugang zu diesem und mehr als 300000 Büchern ab EUR 5,99 monatlich.
Our knowledge comes primarily from experience – what our senses tell us. But is experience really what it seems? The experimental breakthroughs in 17th-century science of Kepler, Galileo and Newton informed the great British empiricist tradition, which accepts a 'common-sense' view of the world – and yet concludes that all we can ever know are 'ideas'. In Introducing Empiricism: A Graphic Guide, Dave Robinson - with the aid of Bill Mayblin's brilliant illustrations - outlines the arguments of Locke, Berkeley, Hume, J.S. Mill, Bertrand Russell and the last British empiricist, A.J. Ayer. They also explore criticisms of empiricism in the work of Kant, Wittgenstein, Karl Popper and others, providing a unique overview of this compelling area of philosophy.
Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:
Seitenzahl: 117
Veröffentlichungsjahr: 2015
Das E-Book (TTS) können Sie hören im Abo „Legimi Premium” in Legimi-Apps auf:
Published by Icon Books Ltd, Omnibus Business Centre, 39–41 North Road, London N7 9DPEmail: [email protected]
ISBN: 978-178578-017-2
Text copyright © 2012 Icon Books Ltd
Illustrations copyright © 2012 Icon Books Ltd
The author and illustrator has asserted their moral rights
Originating editor: Richard Appignanesi
No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, or by any means, without prior permission in writing from the publisher.
Cover
Title Page
Copyright
What is Empiricism?
Knowledge and Belief
Inside and Outside
Originals and Copies
Questions Lead to Uncertainty
To Begin at the Beginning
Aristotle and Observation
Medieval Scholasticism
New Ways of Thinking
Rationalists and Empiricists
Logic and a Deeper Reality?
Francis Bacon
Empiricist Ants and Rationalist Spiders
Scientific Bees and Induction
Bacon, Scientism and Thomas Hobbes
Hobbes’s Leviathan
Hobbes the Empiricist
Locke and Empiricist Theory
Innate Ideas on Blank Sheets
The Empiricist Account
Direct Realism
Differences of Property and Experience
Appearances Are All We Have
Responding to Scepticism
Representative Realism
Mental Images
Simple Ideas
Mental Jamjars
Complex Ideas
Problems of Reflection
Primary and Secondary Qualities
The Philosophy of Corpuscles
Secondary Qualities
Subjective Objects of Sense
Substances Underlying Qualities
The Word “Idea” and Concepts
Concepts as Images
Looking and Thinking
Language as Ideational
Abstract Ideas
Nominal and Real Essences
Identity in Time
Personal Identity
Locke’s Politics
The Legacy of Locke’s Empiricism
Was He Right?
The Prodigy
Berkeley’s Aims
Ending in Scepticism
Berkeley’s Idealism
Esse est Percipi
A New Theory of Vision
Abstract Ideas
Shape and Colour
Triangles
Images of Particulars
Language
How It All Works
Dr Johnson’s Refutation
Berkeley’s Monist Argument
Imagination and Truth
Purely Mental Existence
The Argument from God
The Existence of the Self
Science Depends on God
Space and Numbers
God and Minds
Is Berkeley Irrefutable?
Are the Arguments Convincing?
Begging the Question
God’s Intervention
The Counter-argument from Evolution
David Hume
Hume’s Philosophy of Scepticism
Ideas and Impressions
Impressions and Truth
The Criteria of Force and Vivacity
The External World
Philosophy and Everyday Life
Hume’s Fork
Science, Theology and Proof
The Problem of Cause and Effect
What is Cause?
The Appearance of Constant Conjunction
What is Necessity?
Cause is Psychological and not Logical
Hume Explains “Why”
Induction and Deduction
Rules of Deductive Logic
The Uses of Induction
Solutions to the Problem
The Response of Pragmatism
What About Identity?
Looking Within
Hume on Free Will
Religion, Proof and Design
Ethics, Moral Language and Fact
Meta-Ethics
Conclusions on Hume
Kant’s Criticism of Hume
J.S. Mill’s Empirical Philosophy
The Permanent Possibility of Sensation
Possible Sensations
Why Do We Believe in Objects?
Problems with Mill’s Position
Mathematics
Mill’s Logic
Induction
Mill’s Treatment of Cause
What are Minds?
Mill’s Ethics and Politics
Higher Pleasures
Mill’s Politics
Bertrand Russell
Relative Perception
Sense Data
Russell’s Theory of Knowledge
Logical Atomism
Meaning and Atomic Facts
Mathematics and Logic
A.J. Ayer and the Vienna Circle
Meaning and Logical Positivism
Language Bewitchment
The Isness of Is
Ayer’s Phenomenalism
The A Priori Tautologies
Is This Correct?
Analytic Philosophy
What of Religion?
And Ethics?
Problems with Verificationism
Ayer’s Theory of Meaning
Meaning as Use
The Doctrine Examined
Knowledge Claims
The Foundations of Empiricism
Images as Sense Knowledge
The Knowledge Building
What Does Science Tell Us?
The Person Inside the Head
The Argument from Observer Relativity
Questions of Reliability
A Private World of Representations
How Real Are Sense Data?
The Adverbial Solution
Perceptions as Beliefs
Immediacy
Looking and Seeing
Logical and Psychological Processes
What Do We See?
The Private Language Argument
Public Language
Wittgenstein’s Criticism
The Outside Within Experience
Knowledge in the World
The Power of Knowledge
Kant on Perception
The Kantian Categories
Conceptual Frameworks
Language and Experience
Making Our World
Empiricism Denied
British and European Philosophy
The Unknowable Mind
A Future for Empiricism?
Further Reading
About the Author
Acknowledgements
Index
THIS BOOK IS ABOUT EMPIRICIST PHILOSOPHERS WHO BELIEVE THAT HUMAN KNOWLEDGE HAS TO COME FROM OBSERVATION. MOST EMPIRICISTS THINK THAT IT’S QUITE POSSIBLE THAT ONLY WE EXIST, AND NOTHING ELSE.
I’m sitting at my computer, after a long day, beginning the first few pages of this book, when without any warning a huge, leathery hippopotamus walks into the room.
THEN I WAKE UP. I’VE BEEN DREAMING. I LOOK AROUND ME, AND THE COMPUTER’S STILL HERE. SO ARE ALL MY BOOKS, GLASSES, A JAR FULL OF PENS, AND A MUG OF COLD TEA. THE SUN IS SHINING OUTSIDE, AND THE TREES ARE MOVING IN THE WIND.
Now I’m confident that I’m awake. Everything I see, hear, smell, touch and taste is real, this time. Knowing about the world through the senses is the most primitive sort of knowledge there is. I couldn’t function without it. But is it possible that I am mistaken, just as I was about the hippopotamus? How certain can I be about my perceptions of trees, jamjars and that cup of cold tea?
Most people assume that the world is pretty much as it appears to them. They believe a cat exists when they see it cross the road. But philosophers are, notoriously, more demanding. They say that beliefs are plentiful, cheap and easy, but true knowledge is more limited, and much harder to justify. This is why philosophers normally begin by separating knowledge from belief.
I PERSONALLY BELIEVE IN THE CONTINUED EXISTENCE OF THIS ROOM AND THE GARDEN OUTSIDE, BUT NOT IN THAT HIPPOPOTAMUS. I ALSO THINK MY BELIEFS ABOUT THE REALITY OF MY IMMEDIATE SURROUNDINGS ARE JUSTIFIED BECAUSE THEY SEEM NATURAL, NORMAL AND OBVIOUS.
That’s enough to convert my beliefs into knowledge. But there is always a slight possibility that I am wrong. The world might not be as I believe it to be. Problems like these worry philosophers called “empiricists”, because they think that private sensory experiences are virtually all we’ve got, and that they’re the primary source of all human knowledge.
One thing we do know is that our senses sometimes mislead us. White walls can appear yellow in strong sunlight. Surgeons can stimulate my brain so that I “see” a patch of red that isn’t there. I can have hippopotamus dreams, and so on. My sense experiences are at least sometimes created by my mind – or somehow in my mind. These comparatively rare “mistakes” have led many philosophers to insist that all my perceptions are “mediated”.
WHEN I LOOK OUT OF THE WINDOW, AT THOSE TREES, IT SEEMS TO ME THAT I SEE THEM AS THEY ARE, DIRECTLY.
But I don’t. What I see is a wonderful illusion created by my mind. Of course, I am totally unaware of that fact because my perceptions seem so natural, automatic and rapid. Psychologists tell me that what I actually see is a kind of internal picture, and they devise all sorts of tests and puzzles to prove it.
They say that the trees provide me with a “tree sensation” in my mind, and it’s that which I see, not the trees themselves. If that is true, then all I ever see are “copies” of those trees, which I assume are very similar in appearance to the originals.
But, if I think about this even harder, then I realize I have no way of telling how accurate these copies are, because I cannot bypass my mind to take another “closer look” at the originals.
Perhaps the original trees are nothing like the cerebral “copies” at all, or worse still, don’t even exist!
The more I think about perception, the weirder it becomes, and the more I realise that I must be trapped in my own private world of perceptions that may tell me nothing about what is “out there”.
PERHAPS THERE’S JUST ME, AND NOTHING ELSE! SUDDENLY I FEEL DIZZY.
This kind of unnerving conclusion is typical of philosophy. You ask simple questions which lead to unsettling bizarre answers.
THAT WHICH I KNEW, I NOW DO NOT KNOW AT ALL. SO IS THERE ANYTHING AT ALL I CAN BE SURE ABOUT?
If there isn’t, how can empiricist philosophers claim that all human knowledge comes from experience? If no one can ever be sure where “experiences” come from in the first place, how reliable are they?
Empiricist philosophy is relatively new. Philosophy as such began very differently, with some ancient Greeks called “Pre-Socratic” philosophers who emphasized the differences between appearance and reality. They said that what we see tells us very little about what is real. True knowledge can only come from thinking, not looking. The first truly systematic philosopher, Plato (427–347 B.C.E.), agreed that empirical or sense knowledge is inferior because it is subjective and always changing.
I ONLY BELIEVE THOSE TREES ARE “BIG” BECAUSE THEY’RE SLIGHTLY TALLER THAN MY HOUSE. MY “KNOWLEDGE” OF THOSE TREES IS WHOLLY RELATIVE TO ME. WHAT KIND OF KNOWLEDGE IS THAT? EMPIRICAL KNOWLEDGE CAN ONLY EVER BE A MATTER OF “OPINION” OR “BELIEF”.
Plato turned to mathematics instead. Unlike my trees, numbers are abstract, immune from physical change, the same for everyone, and have a permanence, certainty and objectivity that empirical knowledge lacks. Plato believed that real knowledge had to be like mathematics, timeless and cerebral.
Plato’s famous student, Aristotle (384–322 B.C.E.), disagreed. He thought that it was important to observe the world as well as do mathematics.
I TRIED TO SHOW HOW ALL NATURAL THINGS FUNCTION AS A RESULT OF THE DIFFERENT CAUSES THAT AFFECT THEM.
Aristotle was not a very methodical scientist by our standards. His observations were often tailored to fit his complex metaphysical theories. Much of what he called “physics” was proved wrong.
Aristotle’s works resurfaced via Arabic scholarship in 12th-century Western Europe and eventually dominated medieval intellectual life. Western scholars were overawed by the apparent intellectual superiority of Greek philosophy and timidly assumed that human knowledge was virtually complete.
IN THE 13TH CENTURY, I RECONCILED ARISTOTELIAN PHILOSOPHY WITH CHRISTIAN THEOLOGY.
This strange synthesis devised by the Dominican cleric St Thomas Aquinas (1225–74) was subsequently taught in the medieval “schools” or universities and became known as “Scholasticism”. Everyone imagined that philosophy and science had more or less reached a dead-end of perfection.
Medieval science was more concerned with words and definitions than systematic observation of the world. Attitudes began to change in the 16th and 17th centuries. The Reformation helped to loosen the grip of the Church on intellectual life. Modern scientists like Johannes Kepler (1571–1630) and Galileo Galilei (1564–1642) discovered that the universe was not at all as Aristotle had described it. The founder of modern philosophy, René Descartes (1596–1650), described an entirely new kind of science.
CERTAIN KNOWLEDGE DEPENDS ON INTROSPECTION WHICH RECOGNIZES A FEW “CLEAR AND DISTINCT” IDEAS AS NECESSARILY TRUE.
Descartes, like Plato, remained a “Rationalist” philosopher, convinced that scientific knowledge had to derive from mathematics and logic. He was nevertheless a major influence on empiricist philosophers.
The Cartesian model of the mind as a kind of “private room”, and his corresponding theories of perception, reality, knowledge and certainty, seemed persuasive to most empiricist philosophers.
WE ONLY EVER PERCEIVE PRIVATE IDEAS, RATHER THAN THE OUTSIDE WORLD. KNOWLEDGE HAS TO BE ASSEMBLED GRADUALLY, FROM THE INSIDE OUT.
Rationalist philosophers maintain that reason is the most reliable source of knowledge. “Knowledge comes from thinking, not looking.”
Geometry provides the best systematic example of infallible, permanent knowledge based wholly on deduction. But empiricists” claim that, although geometrical and mathematical forms of knowledge are “necessary”, they are only reliable because they are “trivial”. Logic and mathematics do no more than “unpack” or clarify the inevitable consequences of a few preliminary definitions or axioms.
THE ANGLES OF A TRIANGLE HAVE TO ADD UP TO 180 DEGREES – IF YOU ACCEPT THAT THE SHORTEST DISTANCE BETWEEN TWO POINTS IS A STRAIGHT LINE, AND A FEW OTHER AXIOMS. AND, IF ALL CATS HAVE WHISKERS, AND THIS IS A CAT, THEN IT MUST HAVE WHISKERS. BUT THIS IS A CONCLUSION DERIVED FROM WORDS, NOT CATS.
Empiricists say that neither geometry nor logic will tell you anything about the real world. The cerebral wonders of mathematics and logic are like chess – “closed” and “empty” systems constituted by their own sets of rules.
REAL KNOWLEDGE HAS TO ORIGINATE FROM SENSORY EXPERIENCES AS OUR ONLY GUIDE TO WHAT IS ACTUALLY TRUE.
There is no magical way of going beyond the limits of what we can see, hear, taste, smell and touch.
Later historians have often imagined a kind of “war” between the down to earth British “Empiricists” like Locke, Berkeley and Hume, and the more fanciful “Rationalist” continentals, like Descartes, Spinoza and Leibniz. But this controversy was not very real for those supposedly taking part. Few would have considered themselves stuck in either opposed “camp”. The labels “Empiricist” and “Rationalist”, although useful, can obscure the actual views of individual philosophers.
Francis Bacon (1561–1626) was a lawyer who eventually became Lord Chancellor. He was a corrupt politician, as well as a devoted scholar. He was obsessed with learning, of all kinds, and put forward several schemes for public libraries, laboratories and colleges. (The most famous is “Solomon’s House” in his book New Atlantis.) Bacon believed in scientific progress, even though he was constantly aware of the limitations of human knowledge.
MEN MUST SOBERLY AND MODESTLY DISTINGUISH BETWEEN THINGS DIVINE AND HUMAN, BETWEEN THE ORACLES OF SENSE AND FAITH.
Bacon thought that a methodical and detailed observation of the world would massively increase the scope of human knowledge. It was only by studying the world’s complex design that we would learn about its designer, God.
Bacon was scathing about scholars who worshipped past “authorities” and obscured the “advancement of learning”. Medieval “scientists” spent too long in libraries, arguing about definitions. Real science meant investigating the world outside.
BUT THERE IS MORE TO SCIENCE THAN ACCUMULATING FACTS. KNOWLEDGE CAN ONLY ADVANCE WHEN OBSERVATIONS HAVE SOME POINT TO THEM.
Successful “natural philosophers” are like sensible “bees”. Their methodical collections of information stimulate theory, give rise to experiments, and produce the “honey” of scientific wisdom. Bacon devised a whole series of procedural methods for ambitious bee-scientists.
I RECOGNIZED THE IMPORTANCE OF INDUCTION AS A METHOD OF RESEARCH AND A WAY OF STIMULATING THEORY.