1,99 €
The main purpose of this essay is to show that natural language, when contextualised, by its nature avoids the paradoxes and the shortcomings ascribed to it. Preliminarily, I would like to put forward some hypotheses on the origin of language based on hypotheses inferred, in my opinion, in the writings of the American linguist, Noam Chomsky, and the American philosopher, Jerry Fodor. I also propose a simple, naturalist hypothesis on the origin of natural numbers and therefore of arithmetic.
Das E-Book können Sie in Legimi-Apps oder einer beliebigen App lesen, die das folgende Format unterstützen:
PREFACE
1) EDUCATION
2) EXIT FROM THE GARDEN OF EDEN
3) THE INVENTION OF LANGUAGE
4) CHARACTERISTICS OF LANGUAGE
5) THE FUNCTION OF NATURAL LANGUAGE
6) THE FUNCTION OF FORMALISED LANGUAGE
7) LINGUISTIC PARADOXES
8) SET THEORY
9) ARITHMETIC
10) CONCLUSION
Lario Sinigaglia
LANGUAGE:
A DIFFERENT USE OF THE BRAIN
Youcanprint
Title | Language: a different use of the brain
Author |Ilario Sinigaglia
ISBN |9788831633420
Prima edizione digitale: 2019
© Tutti i diritti riservati all'Autore.
Questa opera è pubblicata direttamente dall'autore tramite la piattaforma di selfpublishing Youcanprint e l'autore detiene ogni diritto della stessa in maniera esclusiva. Nessuna parte di questo libro può essere pertanto riprodotta senza il preventivo assenso dell'autore.
Youcanprint Self-Publishing
Via Marco Biagi 6, 73100 Lecce
www.youcanprint.it
Qualsiasi distribuzione o fruizione non autorizzata costituisce violazione dei diritti dell’autore e sarà sanzionata civilmente e penalmente secondo quanto previsto dalla legge 633/1941.
The main purpose of this essay is to show that natural language, when contextualised, by its nature avoids the paradoxes and the shortcomings ascribed to it.
Preliminarily, I would like to put forward some hypotheses on the origin of language based on hypotheses inferred, in my opinion, in the writings of the American linguist, Noam Chomsky, and the American philosopher, Jerry Fodor.
I also propose a simple, naturalist hypothesis on the origin of natural numbers and therefore of arithmetic. Only chapter 8, on set theory, requires some prior knowledge that the reader of goodwill can easily find even in my previous writings which are cited. Chapter 7 dealing with linguistic paradoxes is complex when addressing the difference between concepts and properties and requires some engagement by the reader. My advice is to proceed even if not everything is clear in the first reading. You can reflect and take a second look. Here and elsewhere, we do not understand everything right away. Anyone who wants to understand everything before proceeding, should simply not proceed. Proceed, therefore, and you will understand, if not everything, certainly more. Any text that has been important to me has taken time and several readings. I hope that my writing is worth the effort of the reader.
Lario Sinigaglia
A small child of a few years speaks, at ten they write correctly, and at 14 they can be held criminally liable and therefore are expected to know the rules of civilised life. These are the results of a thorough education provided in a civil context. But how did this all begin?
Darwinian evolution follows Homo sapiens back to about 200,000 years ago and, since we are also Homo sapiens, he could have been our grandfather who, even though he did not speak, did not write, nor use utensils and was therefore certainly much smarter than our actual grandfather in managing with his bare hands in an unimaginably hostile environment.
According to Noam Chomsky (1928), the great scholar of language, Homo sapiens began to speak quite suddenly around 60,000 years ago and he bases this hypothesis on the emergence at that time of archaeological finds that demonstrate the ability to symbolise the circumstances of human life, relatively complex societies, as well as the population’s greater dynamism for growth and migration (Noam Chomsky and James McGilvray, The Science of Language. Interviews with James McGilvray, 2012, Italian translation published by Il Saggiatore, Milan 2015).
We therefore follow Chomsky as much for the depth of his studies on language as for the implicit assumption that the linguistic path is the most important one for understanding humans: after all, it is the only characteristic that separates them from the universe of other living beings.
Chomsky admits, however, that the conquest of language was preceded by brain activity which he characterised as Merge (to merge: to add, incorporate, blend together), which is preliminary to the typical compositionality of language.
All these are of course the famous professor’s hypotheses and we should abound in the use of the conditional to put them forward (as Chomsky himself does: it would have been preceded... etc.). But I like the professor’s hypotheses and I will therefore use the indicative, reserving the conditional for my own hypotheses.
But what does the brain merge and incorporate? Certainly not words, which do not exist, nor simply images, as every higher animal has certainly done for a long time.
Perhaps it merges “experiences”.
Let us return briefly to the present since it remains the best way to explain a past that basically never dies.
Experiences are generally considered a value, but, as we shall see, they have an ambiguous value because you pay for them with the painful currency of mistakes.
It is impossible to gain experiences without making mistakes and we gain experiences only by surviving mistakes.
Training and contraptions of experience simulators can be used but, ultimately, reality is different.
Different from what? From what we thought it was according to information at our disposal.
Let’s go back to 200,000 years ago: Homo sapiens actually knew next to nothing of what we learn in school today. But, if they managed to survive until then, it is because there was a valid and innate instinctual heritage that was all that they had.
Therefore, to gain experience (since today we gain experience, in the beginning they did the same), to gain experience, one must, at least in part, falsify one’s own instinctual heritage. That is, behave differently from how instinct tells us to, for example handling fire.