Saint Aquinas Thomas
Summa Theologica Book I
UUID: 1b395528-6424-11e5-bb24-119a1b5d0361
This ebook was created with StreetLib Write (http://write.streetlib.com)by Simplicissimus Book Farm
Table of contents
PROLOGUE
SUMMA THEOLOGICA
QUESTION 1
QUESTION 2
QUESTION 3
QUESTION 4
QUESTION 5
QUESTION 6
QUESTION 7
QUESTION 8
QUESTION 9
QUESTION 10
QUESTION 11
QUESTION 12
QUESTION 13
QUESTION 14
QUESTION 15
QUESTION 16
QUESTION 17
QUESTION 18
QUESTION 19
QUESTION 20
QUESTION 21
QUESTION 22
QUESTION 23
QUESTION 24
QUESTION 25
QUESTION 26
QUESTION 27
QUESTION 28
QUESTION 29
QUESTION 30
QUESTION 31
QUESTION 32
QUESTION 33
QUESTION 34
QUESTION 35
QUESTION 36
QUESTION 37
QUESTION 38
QUESTION 39
QUESTION 40
QUESTION 41
QUESTION 42
QUESTION 43
QUESTION 44
QUESTION 45
QUESTION 46
QUESTION 47
QUESTION 48
QUESTION 49
QUESTION 50
QUESTION 51
QUESTION 52
QUESTION 53
QUESTION 54
QUESTION 55
QUESTION 56
QUESTION 57
QUESTION 58
QUESTION 59
QUESTION 60
QUESTION 61
QUESTION 62
QUESTION 63
QUESTION 64
QUESTION 65
QUESTION 66
QUESTION 67
QUESTION 68
QUESTION 69
QUESTION 70
QUESTION 71
QUESTION 72
QUESTION 73
QUESTION 74
QUESTION 75
QUESTION 76
QUESTION 77
QUESTION 78
QUESTION 79
QUESTION 80
QUESTION 81
QUESTION 82
QUESTION 83
QUESTION 84
QUESTION 85
QUESTION 86
QUESTION 87
QUESTION 88
QUESTION 89
QUESTION 90
QUESTION 91
QUESTION 92
QUESTION 93
QUESTION 94
QUESTION 95
QUESTION 96
QUESTION 97
QUESTION 98
QUESTION 99
QUESTION 100
QUESTION 101
QUESTION 102
QUESTION 103
QUESTION 104
QUESTION 105
QUESTION 106
QUESTION 107
QUESTION 108
QUESTION 109
QUESTION 110
QUESTION 111
QUESTION 112
QUESTION 113
QUESTION 114
QUESTION 115
QUESTION 117
QUESTION 118
QUESTION 119
PROLOGUE
Because
the Master of Catholic Truth ought not only to teach the proficient,
but also to instruct beginners (according to the Apostle: As Unto
Little Ones in Christ, I Gave You Milk to Drink, Not Meat— 1 Cor.
iii. 1, 2)—we purpose in this book to treat of whatever belongs to
the Christian Religion, in such a way as may tend to the instruction
of beginners. We have considered that students in this Science have
not seldom been hampered by what they have found written by other
authors, partly on account of the multiplication of useless
questions, articles, and arguments; partly also because those things
that are needful for them to know are not taught according to the
order of the subject-matter, but according as the plan of the book
might require, or the occasion of the argument offer; partly, too,
because frequent repetition brought weariness and confusion to the
minds of the readers.Endeavoring
to avoid these and other like faults, we shall try, by God's help, to
set forth whatever is included in this Sacred Science as briefly and
clearly as the matter itself may allow.
SUMMA THEOLOGICA
FIRST
PART["I," "Prima Pars"]
QUESTION 1
THE
NATURE AND EXTENT OF SACRED DOCTRINE (in Ten Articles)To
place our purpose within proper limits, we first endeavor to
investigate the nature and extent of this sacred doctrine. Concerning
this there are ten points of inquiry:(1)
Whether it is necessary?(2)
Whether it is a science?(3)
Whether it is one or many?(4)
Whether it is speculative or practical?(5)
How it is compared with other sciences?(6)
Whether it is the same as wisdom?(7)
Whether God is its subject-matter?(8)
Whether it is a matter of argument?(9)
Whether it rightly employs metaphors and similes?(10)
Whether the Sacred Scripture of this doctrine may be expounded in
different senses? _______________________FIRST
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 1]Whether,
besides Philosophy, any Further Doctrine Is Required?Objection
1: It seems that, besides philosophical science, we have no need of
any further knowledge. For man should not seek to know what is above
reason: "Seek not the things that are too high for thee"
(Ecclus. 3:22). But whatever is not above reason is fully treated of
in philosophical science. Therefore any other knowledge besides
philosophical science is superfluous.Obj.
2: Further, knowledge can be concerned only with being, for nothing
can be known, save what is true; and all that is, is true. But
everything that is, is treated of in philosophical science—even God
Himself; so that there is a part of philosophy called theology, or
the divine science, as Aristotle has proved (Metaph. vi). Therefore,
besides philosophical science, there is no need of any further
knowledge.On
the contrary, It is
written (2 Tim. 3:16): "All Scripture inspired of God is
profitable to teach, to reprove, to correct, to instruct in justice."
Now Scripture, inspired of God, is no part of philosophical science,
which has been built up by human reason. Therefore it is useful that
besides philosophical science, there should be other knowledge, i.e.
inspired of God.I
answer that, It was
necessary for man's salvation that there should be a knowledge
revealed by God besides philosophical science built up by human
reason. Firstly, indeed, because man is directed to God, as to an end
that surpasses the grasp of his reason: "The eye hath not seen,
O God, besides Thee, what things Thou hast prepared for them that
wait for Thee" (Isa. 66:4). But the end must first be known by
men who are to direct their thoughts and actions to the end. Hence it
was necessary for the salvation of man that certain truths which
exceed human reason should be made known to him by divine revelation.
Even as regards those truths about God which human reason could have
discovered, it was necessary that man should be taught by a divine
revelation; because the truth about God such as reason could
discover, would only be known by a few, and that after a long time,
and with the admixture of many errors. Whereas man's whole salvation,
which is in God, depends upon the knowledge of this truth. Therefore,
in order that the salvation of men might be brought about more fitly
and more surely, it was necessary that they should be taught divine
truths by divine revelation. It was therefore necessary that besides
philosophical science built up by reason, there should be a sacred
science learned through revelation.Reply
Obj. 1: Although those things which are beyond man's knowledge may
not be sought for by man through his reason, nevertheless, once they
are revealed by God, they must be accepted by faith. Hence the sacred
text continues, "For many things are shown to thee above the
understanding of man" (Ecclus. 3:25). And in this, the sacred
science consists.Reply
Obj. 2: Sciences are differentiated according to the various means
through which knowledge is obtained. For the astronomer and the
physicist both may prove the same conclusion: that the earth, for
instance, is round: the astronomer by means of mathematics (i.e.
abstracting from matter), but the physicist by means of matter
itself. Hence there is no reason why those things which may be
learned from philosophical science, so far as they can be known by
natural reason, may not also be taught us by another science so far
as they fall within revelation. Hence theology included in sacred
doctrine differs in kind from that theology which is part of
philosophy. _______________________SECOND
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 2]Whether
Sacred Doctrine Is a Science?Objection
1: It seems that sacred doctrine is not a science. For every science
proceeds from self-evident principles. But sacred doctrine proceeds
from articles of faith which are not self-evident, since their truth
is not admitted by all: "For all men have not faith" (2
Thess. 3:2). Therefore sacred doctrine is not a science.Obj.
2: Further, no science deals with individual facts. But this sacred
science treats of individual facts, such as the deeds of Abraham,
Isaac and Jacob and such like. Therefore sacred doctrine is not a
science.On
the contrary,
Augustine says (De Trin. xiv, 1) "to this science alone belongs
that whereby saving faith is begotten, nourished, protected and
strengthened." But this can be said of no science except sacred
doctrine. Therefore sacred doctrine is a science.I
answer that, Sacred
doctrine is a science. We must bear in mind that there are two kinds
of sciences. There are some which proceed from a principle known by
the natural light of intelligence, such as arithmetic and geometry
and the like. There are some which proceed from principles known by
the light of a higher science: thus the science of perspective
proceeds from principles established by geometry, and music from
principles established by arithmetic. So it is that sacred doctrine
is a science because it proceeds from principles established by the
light of a higher science, namely, the science of God and the
blessed. Hence, just as the musician accepts on authority the
principles taught him by the mathematician, so sacred science is
established on principles revealed by God.Reply
Obj. 1: The principles of any science are either in themselves
self-evident, or reducible to the conclusions of a higher science;
and such, as we have said, are the principles of sacred doctrine.Reply
Obj. 2: Individual facts are treated of in sacred doctrine, not
because it is concerned with them principally, but they are
introduced rather both as examples to be followed in our lives (as in
moral sciences) and in order to establish the authority of those men
through whom the divine revelation, on which this sacred scripture or
doctrine is based, has come down to us. _______________________THIRD
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 3]Whether
Sacred Doctrine Is One Science?Objection
1: It seems that sacred doctrine is not one science; for according to
the Philosopher (Poster. i) "that science is one which treats
only of one class of subjects." But the creator and the
creature, both of whom are treated of in sacred doctrine, cannot be
grouped together under one class of subjects. Therefore sacred
doctrine is not one science.Obj.
2: Further, in sacred doctrine we treat of angels, corporeal
creatures and human morality. But these belong to separate
philosophical sciences. Therefore sacred doctrine cannot be one
science.On
the contrary, Holy
Scripture speaks of it as one science: "Wisdom gave him the
knowledge [scientiam] of holy things" (Wis. 10:10).I
answer that, Sacred
doctrine is one science. The unity of a faculty or habit is to be
gauged by its object, not indeed, in its material aspect, but as
regards the precise formality under which it is an object. For
example, man, ass, stone agree in the one precise formality of being
colored; and color is the formal object of sight. Therefore, because
Sacred Scripture considers things precisely under the formality of
being divinely revealed, whatever has been divinely revealed
possesses the one precise formality of the object of this science;
and therefore is included under sacred doctrine as under one science.Reply
Obj. 1: Sacred doctrine does not treat of God and creatures equally,
but of God primarily, and of creatures only so far as they are
referable to God as their beginning or end. Hence the unity of this
science is not impaired.Reply
Obj. 2: Nothing prevents inferior faculties or habits from being
differentiated by something which falls under a higher faculty or
habit as well; because the higher faculty or habit regards the object
in its more universal formality, as the object of the
common sense is
whatever affects the senses, including, therefore, whatever is
visible or audible. Hence the
common sense,
although one faculty, extends to all the objects of the five senses.
Similarly, objects which are the subject-matter of different
philosophical sciences can yet be treated of by this one single
sacred science under one aspect precisely so far as they can be
included in revelation. So that in this way, sacred doctrine bears,
as it were, the stamp of the divine science which is one and simple,
yet extends to everything. _______________________FOURTH
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 4]Whether
Sacred Doctrine Is a Practical Science?Objection
1: It seems that sacred doctrine is a practical science; fora
practical science is that which ends in action according to
thePhilosopher
(Metaph. ii). But sacred doctrine is ordained to action:"Be
ye doers of the word, and not hearers only" (James
1:22).Therefore
sacred doctrine is a practical science.Obj.
2: Further, sacred doctrine is divided into the Old and theNew
Law. But law implies a moral science which is a practical
science.Therefore
sacred doctrine is a practical science.On
the contrary, Every
practical science is concerned with human operations; as moral
science is concerned with human acts, and architecture with
buildings. But sacred doctrine is chiefly concerned with God, whose
handiwork is especially man. Therefore it is not a practical but a
speculative science.I
answer that, Sacred
doctrine, being one, extends to things which belong to different
philosophical sciences because it considers in each the same formal
aspect, namely, so far as they can be known through divine
revelation. Hence, although among the philosophical sciences one is
speculative and another practical, nevertheless sacred doctrine
includes both; as God, by one and the same science, knows both
Himself and His works. Still, it is speculative rather than practical
because it is more concerned with divine things than with human acts;
though it does treat even of these latter, inasmuch as man is
ordained by them to the perfect knowledge of God in which consists
eternal bliss. This is a sufficient answer to the Objections.
_______________________FIFTH
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 5]Whether
Sacred Doctrine Is Nobler than Other Sciences?Objection
1: It seems that sacred doctrine is not nobler than other sciences;
for the nobility of a science depends on the certitude it
establishes. But other sciences, the principles of which cannot be
doubted, seem to be more certain than sacred doctrine; for its
principles—namely, articles of faith—can be doubted. Therefore
other sciences seem to be nobler.Obj.
2: Further, it is the sign of a lower science to depend upon a
higher; as music depends on arithmetic. But sacred doctrine does in a
sense depend upon philosophical sciences; for Jerome observes, in his
Epistle to Magnus, that "the ancient doctors so enriched their
books with the ideas and phrases of the philosophers, that thou
knowest not what more to admire in them, their profane erudition or
their scriptural learning." Therefore sacred doctrine is
inferior to other sciences.On
the contrary, Other
sciences are called the handmaidens of this one: "Wisdom sent
her maids to invite to the tower" (Prov. 9:3).I
answer that, Since
this science is partly speculative and partly practical, it
transcends all others speculative and practical. Now one speculative
science is said to be nobler than another, either by reason of its
greater certitude, or by reason of the higher worth of its
subject-matter. In both these respects this science surpasses other
speculative sciences; in point of greater certitude, because other
sciences derive their certitude from the natural light of human
reason, which can err; whereas this derives its certitude from the
light of divine knowledge, which cannot be misled: in point of the
higher worth of its subject-matter because this science treats
chiefly of those things which by their sublimity transcend human
reason; while other sciences consider only those things which are
within reason's grasp. Of the practical sciences, that one is nobler
which is ordained to a further purpose, as political science is
nobler than military science; for the good of the army is directed to
the good of the State. But the purpose of this science, in so far as
it is practical, is eternal bliss; to which as to an ultimate end the
purposes of every practical science are directed. Hence it is clear
that from every standpoint, it is nobler than other sciences.Reply
Obj. 1: It may well happen that what is in itself the more certain
may seem to us the less certain on account of the weakness of our
intelligence, "which is dazzled by the clearest objects of
nature; as the owl is dazzled by the light of the sun" (Metaph.
ii, lect. i). Hence the fact that some happen to doubt about articles
of faith is not due to the uncertain nature of the truths, but to the
weakness of human intelligence; yet the slenderest knowledge that may
be obtained of the highest things is more desirable than the most
certain knowledge obtained of lesser things, as is said in
de Animalibus xi.Reply
Obj. 2: This science can in a sense depend upon the philosophical
sciences, not as though it stood in need of them, but only in order
to make its teaching clearer. For it accepts its principles not from
other sciences, but immediately from God, by revelation. Therefore it
does not depend upon other sciences as upon the higher, but makes use
of them as of the lesser, and as handmaidens: even so the master
sciences make use of the sciences that supply their materials, as
political of military science. That it thus uses them is not due to
its own defect or insufficiency, but to the defect of our
intelligence, which is more easily led by what is known through
natural reason (from which proceed the other sciences) to that which
is above reason, such as are the teachings of this science.
_______________________SIXTH
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 6]Whether
This Doctrine Is the Same as Wisdom?Objection
1: It seems that this doctrine is not the same as wisdom. For no
doctrine which borrows its principles is worthy of the name of
wisdom; seeing that the wise man directs, and is not directed
(Metaph. i). But this doctrine borrows its principles. Therefore this
science is not wisdom.Obj.
2: Further, it is a part of wisdom to prove the principles of other
sciences. Hence it is called the chief of sciences, as is clear in
Ethic. vi. But this doctrine does not prove the principles of other
sciences. Therefore it is not the same as wisdom.Obj.
3: Further, this doctrine is acquired by study, whereas wisdom is
acquired by God's inspiration; so that it is numbered among the gifts
of the Holy Spirit (Isa. 11:2). Therefore this doctrine is not the
same as wisdom.On
the contrary, It is
written (Deut. 4:6): "This is your wisdom and understanding in
the sight of nations."I
answer that, This
doctrine is wisdom above all human wisdom; not merely in any one
order, but absolutely. For since it is the part of a wise man to
arrange and to judge, and since lesser matters should be judged in
the light of some higher principle, he is said to be wise in any one
order who considers the highest principle in that order: thus in the
order of building, he who plans the form of the house is called wise
and architect, in opposition to the inferior laborers who trim the
wood and make ready the stones: "As a wise architect, I have
laid the foundation" (1 Cor. 3:10). Again, in the order of all
human life, the prudent man is called wise, inasmuch as he directs
his acts to a fitting end: "Wisdom is prudence to a man"
(Prov. 10: 23). Therefore he who considers absolutely the highest
cause of the whole universe, namely God, is most of all called wise.
Hence wisdom is said to be the knowledge of divine things, as
Augustine says (De Trin. xii, 14). But sacred doctrine essentially
treats of God viewed as the highest cause—not only so far as He can
be known through creatures just as philosophers knew Him—"That
which is known of God is manifest in them" (Rom. 1:19)—but
also as far as He is known to Himself alone and revealed to others.
Hence sacred doctrine is especially called wisdom.Reply
Obj. 1: Sacred doctrine derives its principles not from any human
knowledge, but from the divine knowledge, through which, as through
the highest wisdom, all our knowledge is set in order.Reply
Obj. 2: The principles of other sciences either are evident and
cannot be proved, or are proved by natural reason through some other
science. But the knowledge proper to this science comes through
revelation and not through natural reason. Therefore it has no
concern to prove the principles of other sciences, but only to judge
of them. Whatsoever is found in other sciences contrary to any truth
of this science must be condemned as false: "Destroying counsels
and every height that exalteth itself against the knowledge of God"
(2 Cor. 10:4, 5).Reply
Obj. 3: Since judgment appertains to wisdom, the twofold manner of
judging produces a twofold wisdom. A man may judge in one way by
inclination, as whoever has the habit of a virtue judges rightly of
what concerns that virtue by his very inclination towards it. Hence
it is the virtuous man, as we read, who is the measure and rule of
human acts. In another way, by knowledge, just as a man learned in
moral science might be able to judge rightly about virtuous acts,
though he had not the virtue. The first manner of judging divine
things belongs to that wisdom which is set down among the gifts of
the Holy Ghost: "The spiritual man judgeth all things" (1
Cor. 2:15). And Dionysius says (Div. Nom. ii): "Hierotheus is
taught not by mere learning, but by experience of divine things."
The second manner of judging belongs to this doctrine which is
acquired by study, though its principles are obtained by revelation.
_______________________SEVENTH
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 7]Whether
God Is the Object of This Science?Objection
1: It seems that God is not the object of this science. For in every
science, the nature of its object is presupposed. But this science
cannot presuppose the essence of God, for Damascene says (De Fide
Orth. i, iv): "It is impossible to define the essence of God."
Therefore God is not the object of this science.Obj.
2: Further, whatever conclusions are reached in any science must be
comprehended under the object of the science. But in Holy Writ we
reach conclusions not only concerning God, but concerning many other
things, such as creatures and human morality. Therefore God is not
the object of this science.On
the contrary, The
object of the science is that of which it principally treats. But in
this science, the treatment is mainly about God; for it is called
theology, as treating of God. Therefore God is the object of this
science.I
answer that, God is
the object of this science. The relation between a science and its
object is the same as that between a habit or faculty and its object.
Now properly speaking, the object of a faculty or habit is the thing
under the aspect of which all things are referred to that faculty or
habit, as man and stone are referred to the faculty of sight in that
they are colored. Hence colored things are the proper objects of
sight. But in sacred science, all things are treated of under the
aspect of God: either because they are God Himself or because they
refer to God as their beginning and end. Hence it follows that God is
in very truth the object of this science. This is clear also from the
principles of this science, namely, the articles of faith, for faith
is about God. The object of the principles and of the whole science
must be the same, since the whole science is contained virtually in
its principles. Some, however, looking to what is treated of in this
science, and not to the aspect under which it is treated, have
asserted the object of this science to be something other than
God—that is, either things and signs; or the works of salvation; or
the whole Christ, as the head and members. Of all these things, in
truth, we treat in this science, but so far as they have reference to
God.Reply
Obj. 1: Although we cannot know in what consists the essence of God,
nevertheless in this science we make use of His effects, either of
nature or of grace, in place of a definition, in regard to whatever
is treated of in this science concerning God; even as in some
philosophical sciences we demonstrate something about a cause from
its effect, by taking the effect in place of a definition of the
cause.Reply
Obj. 2: Whatever other conclusions are reached in this sacred science
are comprehended under God, not as parts or species or accidents but
as in some way related to Him. _______________________EIGHTH
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 8]Whether
Sacred Doctrine is a Matter of Argument?Objection
1: It seems this doctrine is not a matter of argument. For Ambrose
says (De Fide 1): "Put arguments aside where faith is sought."
But in this doctrine, faith especially is sought: "But these
things are written that you may believe" (John 20:31). Therefore
sacred doctrine is not a matter of argument.Obj.
2: Further, if it is a matter of argument, the argument is either
from authority or from reason. If it is from authority, it seems
unbefitting its dignity, for the proof from authority is the weakest
form of proof. But if it is from reason, this is unbefitting its end,
because, according to Gregory (Hom. 26), "faith has no merit in
those things of which human reason brings its own experience."
Therefore sacred doctrine is not a matter of argument.On
the contrary, The
Scripture says that a bishop should "embrace that faithful word
which is according to doctrine, that he may be able to exhort in
sound doctrine and to convince the gainsayers" (Titus 1:9).I
answer that, As
other sciences do not argue in proof of their principles, but argue
from their principles to demonstrate other truths in these sciences:
so this doctrine does not argue in proof of its principles, which are
the articles of faith, but from them it goes on to prove something
else; as the Apostle from the resurrection of Christ argues in proof
of the general resurrection (1 Cor. 15). However, it is to be borne
in mind, in regard to the philosophical sciences, that the inferior
sciences neither prove their principles nor dispute with those who
deny them, but leave this to a higher science; whereas the highest of
them, viz. metaphysics, can dispute with one who denies its
principles, if only the opponent will make some concession; but if he
concede nothing, it can have no dispute with him, though it can
answer his objections. Hence Sacred Scripture, since it has no
science above itself, can dispute with one who denies its principles
only if the opponent admits some at least of the truths obtained
through divine revelation; thus we can argue with heretics from texts
in Holy Writ, and against those who deny one article of faith, we can
argue from another. If our opponent believes nothing of divine
revelation, there is no longer any means of proving the articles of
faith by reasoning, but only of answering his objections—if he has
any—against faith. Since faith rests upon infallible truth, and
since the contrary of a truth can never be demonstrated, it is clear
that the arguments brought against faith cannot be demonstrations,
but are difficulties that can be answered.Reply
Obj. 1: Although arguments from human reason cannot avail to prove
what must be received on faith, nevertheless, this doctrine argues
from articles of faith to other truths.Reply
Obj. 2: This doctrine is especially based upon arguments from
authority, inasmuch as its principles are obtained by revelation:
thus we ought to believe on the authority of those to whom the
revelation has been made. Nor does this take away from the dignity of
this doctrine, for although the argument from authority based on
human reason is the weakest, yet the argument from authority based on
divine revelation is the strongest. But sacred doctrine makes use
even of human reason, not, indeed, to prove faith (for thereby the
merit of faith would come to an end), but to make clear other things
that are put forward in this doctrine. Since therefore grace does not
destroy nature but perfects it, natural reason should minister to
faith as the natural bent of the will ministers to charity. Hence the
Apostle says: "Bringing into captivity every understanding unto
the obedience of Christ" (2 Cor. 10:5). Hence sacred doctrine
makes use also of the authority of philosophers in those questions in
which they were able to know the truth by natural reason, as Paul
quotes a saying of Aratus: "As some also of your own poets said:
For we are also His offspring" (Acts 17:28). Nevertheless,
sacred doctrine makes use of these authorities as extrinsic and
probable arguments; but properly uses the authority of the canonical
Scriptures as an incontrovertible proof, and the authority of the
doctors of the Church as one that may properly be used, yet merely as
probable. For our faith rests upon the revelation made to the
apostles and prophets who wrote the canonical books, and not on the
revelations (if any such there are) made to other doctors. Hence
Augustine says (Epis. ad Hieron. xix, 1): "Only those books of
Scripture which are called canonical have I learned to hold in such
honor as to believe their authors have not erred in any way in
writing them. But other authors I so read as not to deem everything
in their works to be true, merely on account of their having so
thought and written, whatever may have been their holiness and
learning." _______________________NINTH
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 9]Whether
Holy Scripture Should Use Metaphors?Objection
1: It seems that Holy Scripture should not use metaphors. For that
which is proper to the lowest science seems not to befit this
science, which holds the highest place of all. But to proceed by the
aid of various similitudes and figures is proper to poetry, the least
of all the sciences. Therefore it is not fitting that this science
should make use of such similitudes.Obj.
2: Further, this doctrine seems to be intended to make truth clear.
Hence a reward is held out to those who manifest it: "They that
explain me shall have life everlasting" (Ecclus. 24:31). But by
such similitudes truth is obscured. Therefore, to put forward divine
truths by likening them to corporeal things does not befit this
science.Obj.
3: Further, the higher creatures are, the nearer they approach to the
divine likeness. If therefore any creature be taken to represent God,
this representation ought chiefly to be taken from the higher
creatures, and not from the lower; yet this is often found in
Scriptures.On
the contrary, It is
written (Osee 12:10): "I have multiplied visions, and I have
used similitudes by the ministry of the prophets." But to put
forward anything by means of similitudes is to use metaphors.
Therefore this sacred science may use metaphors.I
answer that, It is
befitting Holy Writ to put forward divine and spiritual truths by
means of comparisons with material things. For God provides for
everything according to the capacity of its nature. Now it is natural
to man to attain to intellectual truths through sensible objects,
because all our knowledge originates from sense. Hence in Holy Writ,
spiritual truths are fittingly taught under the likeness of material
things. This is what Dionysius says (Coel. Hier. i): "We cannot
be enlightened by the divine rays except they be hidden within the
covering of many sacred veils." It is also befitting Holy Writ,
which is proposed to all without distinction of persons—"To
the wise and to the unwise I am a debtor" (Rom. 1:14)—that
spiritual truths be expounded by means of figures taken from
corporeal things, in order that thereby even the simple who are
unable by themselves to grasp intellectual things may be able to
understand it.Reply
Obj. 1: Poetry makes use of metaphors to produce a representation,
for it is natural to man to be pleased with representations. But
sacred doctrine makes use of metaphors as both necessary and useful.Reply
Obj. 2: The ray of divine revelation is not extinguished by the
sensible imagery wherewith it is veiled, as Dionysius says (Coel.
Hier. i); and its truth so far remains that it does not allow the
minds of those to whom the revelation has been made, to rest in the
metaphors, but raises them to the knowledge of truths; and through
those to whom the revelation has been made others also may receive
instruction in these matters. Hence those things that are taught
metaphorically in one part of Scripture, in other parts are taught
more openly. The very hiding of truth in figures is useful for the
exercise of thoughtful minds and as a defense against the ridicule of
the impious, according to the words "Give not that which is holy
to dogs" (Matt. 7:6).Reply
Obj. 3: As Dionysius says, (Coel. Hier. i) it is more fitting that
divine truths should be expounded under the figure of less noble than
of nobler bodies, and this for three reasons. Firstly, because
thereby men's minds are the better preserved from error. For then it
is clear that these things are not literal descriptions of divine
truths, which might have been open to doubt had they been expressed
under the figure of nobler bodies, especially for those who could
think of nothing nobler than bodies. Secondly, because this is more
befitting the knowledge of God that we have in this life. For what He
is not is clearer to us than what He is. Therefore similitudes drawn
from things farthest away from God form within us a truer estimate
that God is above whatsoever we may say or think of Him. Thirdly,
because thereby divine truths are the better hidden from the
unworthy. _______________________TENTH
ARTICLE [I, Q. 1, Art. 10]Whether
in Holy Scripture a Word may have Several Senses?Objection
1: It seems that in Holy Writ a word cannot have several senses,
historical or literal, allegorical, tropological or moral, and
anagogical. For many different senses in one text produce confusion
and deception and destroy all force of argument. Hence no argument,
but only fallacies, can be deduced from a multiplicity of
propositions. But Holy Writ ought to be able to state the truth
without any fallacy. Therefore in it there cannot be several senses
to a word.Obj.
2: Further, Augustine says (De util. cred. iii) that "the Old
Testament has a fourfold division as to history, etiology, analogy
and allegory." Now these four seem altogether different from the
four divisions mentioned in the first objection. Therefore it does
not seem fitting to explain the same word of Holy Writ according to
the four different senses mentioned above.Obj.
3: Further, besides these senses, there is the parabolical, which is
not one of these four.On
the contrary,
Gregory says (Moral. xx, 1): "Holy Writ by the manner of its
speech transcends every science, because in one and the same
sentence, while it describes a fact, it reveals a mystery."I
answer that, The
author of Holy Writ is God, in whose power it is to signify His
meaning, not by words only (as man also can do), but also by things
themselves. So, whereas in every other science things are signified
by words, this science has the property, that the things signified by
the words have themselves also a signification. Therefore that first
signification whereby words signify things belongs to the first
sense, the historical or literal. That signification whereby things
signified by words have themselves also a signification is called the
spiritual sense, which is based on the literal, and presupposes it.
Now this spiritual sense has a threefold division. For as the Apostle
says (Heb. 10:1) the Old Law is a figure of the New Law, and
Dionysius says (Coel. Hier. i) "the New Law itself is a figure
of future glory." Again, in the New Law, whatever our Head has
done is a type of what we ought to do. Therefore, so far as the
things of the Old Law signify the things of the New Law, there is the
allegorical sense; so far as the things done in Christ, or so far as
the things which signify Christ, are types of what we ought to do,
there is the moral sense. But so far as they signify what relates to
eternal glory, there is the anagogical sense. Since the literal sense
is that which the author intends, and since the author of Holy Writ
is God, Who by one act comprehends all things by His intellect, it is
not unfitting, as Augustine says (Confess. xii), if, even according
to the literal sense, one word in Holy Writ should have several
senses.Reply
Obj. 1: The multiplicity of these senses does not produce
equivocation or any other kind of multiplicity, seeing that these
senses are not multiplied because one word signifies several things,
but because the things signified by the words can be themselves types
of other things. Thus in Holy Writ no confusion results, for all the
senses are founded on one—the literal—from which alone can any
argument be drawn, and not from those intended in allegory, as
Augustine says (Epis. 48). Nevertheless, nothing of Holy Scripture
perishes on account of this, since nothing necessary to faith is
contained under the spiritual sense which is not elsewhere put
forward by the Scripture in its literal sense.Reply
Obj. 2: These three—history, etiology, analogy—are grouped under
the literal sense. For it is called history, as Augustine expounds
(Epis. 48), whenever anything is simply related; it is called
etiology when its cause is assigned, as when Our Lord gave the reason
why Moses allowed the putting away of wives—namely, on account of
the hardness of men's hearts; it is called analogy whenever the truth
of one text of Scripture is shown not to contradict the truth of
another. Of these four, allegory alone stands for the three spiritual
senses. Thus Hugh of St. Victor (Sacram. iv, 4 Prolog.) includes the
anagogical under the allegorical sense, laying down three senses
only—the historical, the allegorical, and the tropological.Reply
Obj. 3: The parabolical sense is contained in the literal, for by
words things are signified properly and figuratively. Nor is the
figure itself, but that which is figured, the literal sense. When
Scripture speaks of God's arm, the literal sense is not that God has
such a member, but only what is signified by this member, namely
operative power. Hence it is plain that nothing false can ever
underlie the literal sense of Holy Writ. _______________________
QUESTION 2
THE
EXISTENCE OF GOD(In
Three Articles)
Because
the chief aim of sacred doctrine is to teach the knowledge of God,
not only as He is in Himself, but also as He is the beginning of
things and their last end, and especially of rational creatures, as
is clear from what has been already said, therefore, in our endeavor
to expound this science, we shall treat:
(1)
Of God;
(2)
Of the rational creature's advance towards God;
(3)
Of Christ, Who as man, is our way to God.
In
treating of God there will be a threefold division, for we shall
consider:
(1)
Whatever concerns the Divine Essence;
(2)
Whatever concerns the distinctions of Persons;
(3)
Whatever concerns the procession of creatures from Him.
Concerning
the Divine Essence, we must consider:
(1)
Whether God exists?
(2)
The manner of His existence, or, rather, what is
not the manner of
His existence;
(3)
Whatever concerns His operations—namely, His knowledge, will,
power.
Concerning
the first, there are three points of inquiry:
(1)
Whether the proposition "God exists" is self-evident?
(2)
Whether it is demonstrable?
(3)
Whether God exists? _______________________
FIRST
ARTICLE [I, Q. 2, Art. 1]
Whether
the Existence of God Is Self-Evident?
Objection
1: It seems that the existence of God is self-evident. Now those
things are said to be self-evident to us the knowledge of which is
naturally implanted in us, as we can see in regard to first
principles. But as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. i, 1,3), "the
knowledge of God is naturally implanted in all." Therefore the
existence of God is self-evident.
Obj.
2: Further, those things are said to be self-evident which are known
as soon as the terms are known, which the Philosopher (1 Poster. iii)
says is true of the first principles of demonstration. Thus, when the
nature of a whole and of a part is known, it is at once recognized
that every whole is greater than its part. But as soon as the
signification of the word "God" is understood, it is at
once seen that God exists. For by this word is signified that thing
than which nothing greater can be conceived. But that which exists
actually and mentally is greater than that which exists only
mentally. Therefore, since as soon as the word "God" is
understood it exists mentally, it also follows that it exists
actually. Therefore the proposition "God exists" is
self-evident.
Obj.
3: Further, the existence of truth is self-evident. For whoever
denies the existence of truth grants that truth does not exist: and,
if truth does not exist, then the proposition "Truth does not
exist" is true: and if there is anything true, there must be
truth. But God is truth itself: "I am the way, the truth, and
the life" (John 14:6) Therefore "God exists" is
self-evident.
On
the contrary, No
one can mentally admit the opposite of what is self-evident; as the
Philosopher (Metaph. iv, lect. vi) states concerning the first
principles of demonstration. But the opposite of the proposition "God
is" can be mentally admitted: "The fool said in his heart,
There is no God" (Ps. 52:1). Therefore, that God exists is not
self-evident.
I
answer that, A
thing can be self-evident in either of two ways: on the one hand,
self-evident in itself, though not to us; on the other, self-evident
in itself, and to us. A proposition is self-evident because the
predicate is included in the essence of the subject, as "Man is
an animal," for animal is contained in the essence of man. If,
therefore the essence of the predicate and subject be known to all,
the proposition will be self-evident to all; as is clear with regard
to the first principles of demonstration, the terms of which are
common things that no one is ignorant of, such as being and
non-being, whole and part, and such like. If, however, there are some
to whom the essence of the predicate and subject is unknown, the
proposition will be self-evident in itself, but not to those who do
not know the meaning of the predicate and subject of the proposition.
Therefore, it happens, as Boethius says (Hebdom., the title of which
is: "Whether all that is, is good"), "that there are
some mental concepts self-evident only to the learned, as that
incorporeal substances are not in space." Therefore I say that
this proposition, "God exists," of itself is self-evident,
for the predicate is the same as the subject, because God is His own
existence as will be hereafter shown (Q. 3, Art. 4). Now because we
do not know the essence of God, the proposition is not self-evident
to us; but needs to be demonstrated by things that are more known to
us, though less known in their nature—namely, by effects.
Reply
Obj. 1: To know that God exists in a general and confused way is
implanted in us by nature, inasmuch as God is man's beatitude. For
man naturally desires happiness, and what is naturally desired by man
must be naturally known to him. This, however, is not to know
absolutely that God exists; just as to know that someone is
approaching is not the same as to know that Peter is approaching,
even though it is Peter who is approaching; for many there are who
imagine that man's perfect good which is happiness, consists in
riches, and others in pleasures, and others in something else.
Reply
Obj. 2: Perhaps not everyone who hears this word "God"
understands it to signify something than which nothing greater can be
thought, seeing that some have believed God to be a body. Yet,
granted that everyone understands that by this word "God"
is signified something than which nothing greater can be thought,
nevertheless, it does not therefore follow that he understands that
what the word signifies exists actually, but only that it exists
mentally. Nor can it be argued that it actually exists, unless it be
admitted that there actually exists something than which nothing
greater can be thought; and this precisely is not admitted by those
who hold that God does not exist.
Reply
Obj. 3: The existence of truth in general is self-evident but the
existence of a Primal Truth is not self-evident to us.
_______________________
SECOND
ARTICLE [I, Q. 2, Art. 2]
Whether
It Can Be Demonstrated That God Exists?
Objection
1: It seems that the existence of God cannot be demonstrated. For it
is an article of faith that God exists. But what is of faith cannot
be demonstrated, because a demonstration produces scientific
knowledge; whereas faith is of the unseen (Heb. 11:1). Therefore it
cannot be demonstrated that God exists.
Obj.
2: Further, the essence is the middle term of demonstration. But we
cannot know in what God's essence consists, but solely in what it
does not consist; as Damascene says (De Fide Orth. i, 4). Therefore
we cannot demonstrate that God exists.
Obj.
3: Further, if the existence of God were demonstrated, this could
only be from His effects. But His effects are not proportionate to
Him, since He is infinite and His effects are finite; and between the
finite and infinite there is no proportion. Therefore, since a cause
cannot be demonstrated by an effect not proportionate to it, it seems
that the existence of God cannot be demonstrated.
On
the contrary, The
Apostle says: "The invisible things of Him are clearly seen,
being understood by the things that are made" (Rom. 1:20). But
this would not be unless the existence of God could be demonstrated
through the things that are made; for the first thing we must know of
anything is whether it exists.
I
answer that,
Demonstration can be made in two ways: One is through the cause, and
is called a priori,
and this is to argue from what is prior absolutely. The other is
through the effect, and is called a demonstration
a posteriori; this
is to argue from what is prior relatively only to us. When an effect
is better known to us than its cause, from the effect we proceed to
the knowledge of the cause. And from every effect the existence of
its proper cause can be demonstrated, so long as its effects are
better known to us; because since every effect depends upon its
cause, if the effect exists, the cause must pre-exist. Hence the
existence of God, in so far as it is not self-evident to us, can be
demonstrated from those of His effects which are known to us.
Reply
Obj. 1: The existence of God and other like truths about God, which
can be known by natural reason, are not articles of faith, but are
preambles to the articles; for faith presupposes natural knowledge,
even as grace presupposes nature, and perfection supposes something
that can be perfected. Nevertheless, there is nothing to prevent a
man, who cannot grasp a proof, accepting, as a matter of faith,
something which in itself is capable of being scientifically known
and demonstrated.
Reply
Obj. 2: When the existence of a cause is demonstrated from an effect,
this effect takes the place of the definition of the cause in proof
of the cause's existence. This is especially the case in regard to
God, because, in order to prove the existence of anything, it is
necessary to accept as a middle term the meaning of the word, and not
its essence, for the question of its essence follows on the question
of its existence. Now the names given to God are derived from His
effects; consequently, in demonstrating the existence of God from His
effects, we may take for the middle term the meaning of the word
"God".
Reply
Obj. 3: From effects not proportionate to the cause no perfect
knowledge of that cause can be obtained. Yet from every effect the
existence of the cause can be clearly demonstrated, and so we can
demonstrate the existence of God from His effects; though from them
we cannot perfectly know God as He is in His essence.
_______________________
THIRD
ARTICLE [I, Q. 2, Art. 3]
Whether
God Exists?
Objection
1: It seems that God does not exist; because if one of two contraries
be infinite, the other would be altogether destroyed. But the word
"God" means that He is infinite goodness. If, therefore,
God existed, there would be no evil discoverable; but there is evil
in the world. Therefore God does not exist.
Obj.
2: Further, it is superfluous to suppose that what can be accounted
for by a few principles has been produced by many. But it seems that
everything we see in the world can be accounted for by other
principles, supposing God did not exist. For all natural things can
be reduced to one principle which is nature; and all voluntary things
can be reduced to one principle which is human reason, or will.
Therefore there is no need to suppose God's existence.
On
the contrary, It is
said in the person of God: "I am Who am." (Ex. 3:14)
I
answer that, The
existence of God can be proved in five ways.
The
first and more manifest way is the argument from motion. It is
certain, and evident to our senses, that in the world some things are
in motion. Now whatever is in motion is put in motion by another, for
nothing can be in motion except it is in potentiality to that towards
which it is in motion; whereas a thing moves inasmuch as it is in
act. For motion is nothing else than the reduction of something from
potentiality to actuality. But nothing can be reduced from
potentiality to actuality, except by something in a state of
actuality. Thus that which is actually hot, as fire, makes wood,
which is potentially hot, to be actually hot, and thereby moves and
changes it. Now it is not possible that the same thing should be at
once in actuality and potentiality in the same respect, but only in
different respects. For what is actually hot cannot simultaneously be
potentially hot; but it is simultaneously potentially cold. It is
therefore impossible that in the same respect and in the same way a
thing should be both mover and moved, i.e. that it should move
itself. Therefore, whatever is in motion must be put in motion by
another. If that by which it is put in motion be itself put in
motion, then this also must needs be put in motion by another, and
that by another again. But this cannot go on to infinity, because
then there would be no first mover, and, consequently, no other
mover; seeing that subsequent movers move only inasmuch as they are
put in motion by the first mover; as the staff moves only because it
is put in motion by the hand. Therefore it is necessary to arrive at
a first mover, put in motion by no other; and this everyone
understands to be God.
The
second way is from the nature of the efficient cause. In the world of
sense we find there is an order of efficient causes. There is no case
known (neither is it, indeed, possible) in which a thing is found to
be the efficient cause of itself; for so it would be prior to itself,
which is impossible. Now in efficient causes it is not possible to go
on to infinity, because in all efficient causes following in order,
the first is the cause of the intermediate cause, and the
intermediate is the cause of the ultimate cause, whether the
intermediate cause be several, or only one. Now to take away the
cause is to take away the effect. Therefore, if there be no first
cause among efficient causes, there will be no ultimate, nor any
intermediate cause. But if in efficient causes it is possible to go
on to infinity, there will be no first efficient cause, neither will
there be an ultimate effect, nor any intermediate efficient causes;
all of which is plainly false. Therefore it is necessary to admit a
first efficient cause, to which everyone gives the name of God.
The
third way is taken from possibility and necessity, and runs thus. We
find in nature things that are possible to be and not to be, since
they are found to be generated, and to corrupt, and consequently,
they are possible to be and not to be. But it is impossible for these
always to exist, for that which is possible not to be at some time is
not. Therefore, if everything is possible not to be, then at one time
there could have been nothing in existence. Now if this were true,
even now there would be nothing in existence, because that which does
not exist only begins to exist by something already existing.
Therefore, if at one time nothing was in existence, it would have
been impossible for anything to have begun to exist; and thus even
now nothing would be in existence—which is absurd. Therefore, not
all beings are merely possible, but there must exist something the
existence of which is necessary. But every necessary thing either has
its necessity caused by another, or not. Now it is impossible to go
on to infinity in necessary things which have their necessity caused
by another, as has been already proved in regard to efficient causes.
Therefore we cannot but postulate the existence of some being having
of itself its own necessity, and not receiving it from another, but
rather causing in others their necessity. This all men speak of as
God.
The
fourth way is taken from the gradation to be found in things. Among
beings there are some more and some less good, true, noble and the
like. But more
and less
are predicated of different things, according as they resemble in
their different ways something which is the maximum, as a thing is
said to be hotter according as it more nearly resembles that which is
hottest; so that there is something which is truest, something best,
something noblest and, consequently, something which is uttermost
being; for those things that are greatest in truth are greatest in
being, as it is written in
Metaph. ii. Now the
maximum in any genus is the cause of all in that genus; as fire,
which is the maximum heat, is the cause of all hot things. Therefore
there must also be something which is to all beings the cause of
their being, goodness, and every other perfection; and this we call
God.
The
fifth way is taken from the governance of the world. We see that
things which lack intelligence, such as natural bodies, act for an
end, and this is evident from their acting always, or nearly always,
in the same way, so as to obtain the best result. Hence it is plain
that not fortuitously, but designedly, do they achieve their end. Now
whatever lacks intelligence cannot move towards an end, unless it be
directed by some being endowed with knowledge and intelligence; as
the arrow is shot to its mark by the archer. Therefore some
intelligent being exists by whom all natural things are directed to
their end; and this being we call God.
Reply
Obj. 1: As Augustine says (Enchiridion xi): "Since God is the
highest good, He would not allow any evil to exist in His works,
unless His omnipotence and goodness were such as to bring good even
out of evil." This is part of the infinite goodness of God, that
He should allow evil to exist, and out of it produce good.
Reply
Obj. 2: Since nature works for a determinate end under the direction
of a higher agent, whatever is done by nature must needs be traced
back to God, as to its first cause. So also whatever is done
voluntarily must also be traced back to some higher cause other than
human reason or will, since these can change or fail; for all things
that are changeable and capable of defect must be traced back to an
immovable and self-necessary first principle, as was shown in the
body of the Article. _______________________
QUESTION 3
OF
THE SIMPLICITY OF GOD(In
Eight Articles)
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!
Lesen Sie weiter in der vollständigen Ausgabe!