Erhalten Sie Zugang zu diesem und mehr als 300000 Büchern ab EUR 5,99 monatlich.
Rupert Sheldrake's theory of morphic resonance challenges the fundamental assumptions of modern science. A world-famous biologist, Sheldrake proposes that all self-organizing systems, from crystals to human societies, inherit a collective memory that influences their form and behaviour. Rather than being ruled by fixed laws, nature is essentially habitual. All human beings draw upon a collective human memory, and in turn contribute to it. Even individual memory depends on morphic resonance rather than on physical memory traces stored within the brain. Morphic resonance works through morphic fields, which organize the bodies of plants and animals, coordinate the activities of brains, and underlie mental activity. Minds are extended beyond brains both in space and time. This fully-revised and updated edition of The Presence of the Past summarizes the evidence for Dr Sheldrake's controversial theory, reviews new research, and explores its implications for biology, chemistry, physics, psychology and sociology. In place of the mechanistic worldview that has dominated biology since the nineteenth century, this book offers a revolutionary alternative, and opens up a new understanding of life, minds and evolution.
Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:
Seitenzahl: 773
Das E-Book (TTS) können Sie hören im Abo „Legimi Premium” in Legimi-Apps auf:
OTHER BOOKS BY RUPERT SHELDRAKE
A New Science of Life(1981, 2009)
The Rebirth of Nature(1990)
Seven Experiments That Could Change the World(1994)
Dogs That Know When Their Owners Are Coming Home(1999, 2011)
The Sense of Being Stared At(2003)
With Ralph Abraham and Terence McKenna
Chaos, Creativity and Cosmic Consciousness(2001)
The Evolutionary Mind(2005)
With Matthew Fox
Natural Grace(1996)
The Physics of Angels(1996)
About the Author
Dr Rupert Sheldrakeis a biologist and author of more than 80 scientific papers and ten books, including the bestsellingDogs That Know When Their Owners Are Coming HomeandA New Science of Life. He was a Fellow of Clare College, Cambridge and a Research Fellow of the Royal Society. He has written for various newspapers including theGuardian, where he had a regular monthly column, and for a variety of magazines, includingNew Scientistand theSpectator.
Published in the UK in 2011
by Icon Books Ltd, Omnibus Business Centre,
39–41 North Road, London N7 9DP
email: [email protected]
www.iconbooks.co.uk
First edition published in the UK in 1988 by Collins
This electronic edition published in the UK in 2011 by Icon Books Ltd
ISBN: 978-1-84831-313-2 (ePub format)
ISBN: 978-1-84831-314-9 (Adobe ebook format)
Printed edition (ISBN 978-184831-306-4)
sold in the UK, Europe, South Africa and Asia
by Faber & Faber Ltd, Bloomsbury House,
74–77 Great Russell Street, London WC1B 3DA
or their agents
Printed edition distributed in the UK, Europe, South Africa and Asia
by TBS Ltd, TBS Distribution Centre, Colchester Road,
Frating Green, Colchester CO7 7DW
Printed edition published in Australia in 2011 by Allen & Unwin Pty Ltd,
PO Box 8500, 83 Alexander Street,
Crows Nest, NSW 2065
Text copyright © 1988, 2011 Rupert Sheldrake
The author has asserted his moral rights.
No part of this book may be reproduced in any form, or by any means, without prior permission in writing from the publisher.
Typeset by Marie Doherty
To all my teachers, past and present
Contents
Other books by Rupert Sheldrake
About the Author
Title page
Copyright details
Dedication
PREFACE TO THE 2011 EDITION
ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
INTRODUCTION
The habits of nature
The plan of this book
1 ETERNITY AND EVOLUTION
Evolution in an eternal world
Physical eternity
Evolution
The evolutionary universe
Do the laws of nature evolve?
The growth of habits
2 CHANGELESS LAWS, PERMANENT ENERGY
Intuitions of a timeless reality
The Pythagoreans
Platonism, Aristotelianism and the rise of Western science
From Nicholas of Cusa to Galileo
Descartes and the mechanical philosophy
Atomism and materialism
The Newtonian synthesis
The theory of relativity
Quantum theory
Eternal energy
The survival of eternal laws
Repeatable experiments
3 FROM HUMAN PROGRESS TO UNIVERSAL EVOLUTION
Faith in God’s purposes
Faith in human progress
Progressive evolution
Time for very slow change
The tree of life
The blind watchmaker
Evolving organisms
4 THE NATURE OF PHYSICAL FORMS
The elusiveness of form
Philosophies of form
Platonic physics and chemistry
Platonic biology
Aristotelian biology
Materialistic biology
Morphogenesis
5 THE MYSTERY OF MORPHOGENESIS
The unsolved problem of morphogenesis
Organisms are not preformed
The regeneration of wholeness
The germ-plasm
Entelechy
Selfish genes
Genetic programs
The duality of matter and information
Why genes are overrated
Chemical theories of pattern formation
Organic wholes
6 MORPHOGENETIC FIELDS
Fields of different kinds
Morphogenetic fields
The nature of morphogenetic fields
The evolution of morphogenetic fields
The hypothesis of formative causation
Influence through space and time
Morphic fields
Fields of information
The appearance of new fields
7 FIELDS, MATTER AND MORPHIC RESONANCE
Aether, fields and matter
Atoms and organisms: fields within fields
Morphic fields as probability structures
A provisional hypothesis
Molecular morphic resonance
The structure and morphogenesis of proteins
Experiments on protein folding
Morphic resonance in crystallization
Crystallization experiments
Symmetry and internal resonance
Self-resonance
Quantum physics and morphic fields
8 BIOLOGICAL INHERITANCE
Genes and fields
Mutations
The ‘Lamarckian’ inheritance of acquired characteristics
Epigenetic inheritance
The inheritance of acquired characteristics in fruit flies
Dominant and recessive morphic fields
The morphic fields of instinctive behaviour
The inheritance of behavioural fields
Studies with identical twins
‘Missing heritability’ and the human genome project
Morphic resonance and heredity
9 ANIMAL MEMORY
Morphic resonance and memory
Are memories stored inside the brain?
Habituation
Learning
The transmission of learning by morphic resonance
The evolution of new patterns of behaviour
10 MORPHIC RESONANCE IN HUMAN LEARNING
The acquisition of physical skills
Morphic resonance in language learning
Experimental tests with foreign languages
A test with Morse Code
A possible test with Hindi keyboards
New-field tests
Rising IQ test scores
11 REMEMBERING AND FORGETTING
Behavioural and mental fields
Memories and morphic resonance
Habituation and awareness
Recognizing
Recalling
Brains and memories
The trace theory of memory
Brain damage and loss of memory
The electrical evocation of memories
Forgetting
Memories of past lives
12 MINDS AND BRAINS
Materialism versus dualism
Programs of the brain
Brains and extended minds
Vision
Perceptual fields
Body images and phantom limbs
Extended minds and personal experience
13 THE MORPHIC FIELDS OF ANIMAL SOCIETIES
Animal societies as organisms
Societies of insects
Schools of fish
Flocks of birds
Computer models
The organization of animal societies
Cultural inheritance
14 THE FIELDS OF HUMAN SOCIETIES AND CULTURES
Human societies as organisms
Cultural inheritance
Theories of social and cultural organization
Functionalism and structuralism
Group minds
Collective behaviour
The collective unconscious
Evolutionary psychology
15 MYTHS, RITUALS AND THE INFLUENCE OF TRADITION
Myths and origins
Rituals
Initiations
Traditions, schools, styles and influences
The fields of science
16 THE EVOLUTION OF LIFE
Evolutionary faith
The ambiguity of Darwin
Spontaneous variation
The effects of habit
Natural selection
The evolution of morphic fields
Extinction and atavism
Evolutionary convergences
17 COSMIC EVOLUTION
Science, God and the origin of the universe
The evolution of the known fields of physics
Mathematical universes
Is there a purpose in evolution?
Formative causation and the evolution of physics
Morphic resonance between planets
Dark matter and dark energy
Morphic fields of galaxies
Universal self-resonance
18 CREATIVITY WITHIN A LIVING WORLD
The mystery of creativity
How evolution brings nature back to life
Fields, souls and magic
Creative morphic fields
Habit and creativity
The origin of new fields
The primal field of nature
EPILOGUE
NOTES
REFERENCES
GLOSSARY
Preface
to the 2011 edition
This book argues that memory is inherent in nature. The so-called laws of nature are more like habits. Nature’s memory depends on a process called morphic resonance.
I first proposed this hypothesis in my bookA New Science of Life: The Hypothesis of Formative Causation, published in 1981. In the new edition ofA New Science of Lifepublished in 2009, I discussed recent experimental evidence and new tests for morphic resonance.
In the first edition of this book,The Presence of the Past: Morphic Resonance and the Habits of Nature(1988), I developed this hypothesis further, and explored its implications for the understanding of heredity, memory, psychology, social behaviour, cultural inheritance and evolution, including cosmic evolution. This new edition is revised and updated in the light of discussions, criticisms, further thoughts, new evidence and ongoing developments in physics, cosmology, biology and consciousness studies. Changes in science since the 1980s have made this hypothesis more plausible, rather than less so.
When the hypothesis was first published, it was inevitably controversial. I was not surprised by disagreement, but I was surprised – and relieved – by the fact that even my most vociferous critics came up with no evidence against the hypothesis, nor pointed out any serious logical flaws. Instead, they dismissed this hypothesis asunnecessary.1The unsolved scientific problems to which I drew attention were non-problems, or at least only temporary problems, and they would soon be solved by further research along established lines. Talking about morphic resonance was a waste of time, an unwelcome distraction from the serious business of science.
In the 1980s many scientists were confident that biologists were about to explain the nature of life in molecular terms, especially through the sequencing of genomes. Neuroscientists would soon understand the nature of minds through brain scanning and computer modelling. In the computer sciences, artificial intelligence would soon be created in machines that rivalled and even exceeded the intelligence of humans themselves. In physics, through the imminent development of an ultimate Theory of Everything, the origin of the universe and all material reality in it, including life and mind, would be explained in terms of mathematical formulae – ideally in ‘a single theory that will describe the whole universe’, as Stephen Hawking put it inA Brief History of Time(1988). In his words, this theory would be ‘the ultimate triumph of human reason – for then we would know the mind of God’.
In 1997, the American science writer John Horgan published a book entitledThe End of Science: Facing the Limits of Knowledge in the Twilight of the Scientific Age. After talking to leading scientists in many areas of research, he concluded:
My guess is that this narrative that scientists have woven from their knowledge, this modern myth of creation, will be as viable a hundred or even a thousand years from now as it is today. Why? Because it is true. Moreover given how far science has already come, and given the physical, social and cognitive limits constraining further research, science is unlikely to make any significant additions to the knowledge it has already generated. There will be no great revelations in the future compared to those bestowed upon us by Darwin or Einstein or Watson and Crick.2
Things look very different today. The proud promises of the human genome project have not been fulfilled, despite the immense technical achievement it represented. When the first draft was published in the year 2000, the first surprise was that it contained only about 23,000 genes, far fewer than the 100,000 expected. Sea urchins have more than us, around 26,000, and rice plants 38,000. Moreover, our genome differs very little from that of chimpanzees, and tells us almost nothing about our differences from apes. Billions of dollars were invested in genomics, but the commercial payoff has been minimal.
The predictive value of human genomes turns out to be very limited. Everyone knows that tall parents tend to have tall children, and just by measuring parents and children with tape measures, it is possible to explain about 80 to 90 per cent of the differences in children’s height in terms of their parents’ height. In other words, height is 80 to 90 per cent heritable. Recent studies on the genomes of 30,000 people identified about 50 genes associated with being tall or short. But – shockingly – these genes together accounted for only about 5 per cent of the inheritance of height!3This phenomenon is now called ‘the missing heritability problem’. The same problem has shown up in the genetics of heritable diseases. ‘Hubris has been replaced with concern,’ said Steve Jones, professor of genetics at University College London in 2009. He suggested that continuing the present approach, which puts great faith in the predictive power of the genome, would be ‘throwing good money after bad’.4
Meanwhile, brain scanning and computer modelling have failed to explain the nature of minds, and in consciousness studies there is no agreed solution to the ‘hard problem’, the very existence of consciousness itself. Most predictions about the powers of artificial intelligence have turned out to be fantasies.
Physics too has run into seemingly intractable problems. Superstring and M-theories, with ten and eleven dimensions respectively, take science into completely new territory, and try to explain all reality in terms of vibrating strings billions of times smaller than electrons. It is not even clear what M-theory means. InThe Grand Design(2010), Stephen Hawking confessed: ‘No one seems to know what the “M” stands for. It may be “master”, “miracle” or “mystery”. People are still trying to decipher the nature of M-theory, but that may not be possible.’5Superstring and M-theories are incomplete, have several rival versions and are untestable, at least so far. In science, untestability is a vice, not a virtue. One critic wrote a book calledNot Even Wrong,6and a growing number of eminent scientists are worried that theoretical physics has lost its way.7
Meanwhile, cosmologists have come to the conclusion that known kinds of matter and energy constitute only about 4 per cent of the universe. The rest consists of dark matter and dark energy. The nature of 96 per cent of physical reality is literally obscure.8
Within cosmology, there has been much discussion about the cosmological anthropic principle, which asserts that if the laws and constants of nature had been slightly different at the moment of the Big Bang, biological life could never have emerged, and hence we would not be here to think about it. So did a divine mind fine-tune the laws and constants in the beginning? Many cosmologists prefer to believe that our universe is one of a vast, and perhaps infinite, number of parallel universes, all with different laws and constants. All these other universes actually exist; we just happen to live in the one that has the right conditions for us. Therefore there is no need for a God to fine-tune the laws and constants.
The trouble is that there is no evidence for these extra universes. In the eyes of sceptics, the multiverse theory is the ultimate violation of Occam’s razor, the principle that entities should not be multiplied unnecessarily. And invoking billions of unobserved universes does not even succeed in getting rid of God. An infinite God could be the God of an infinite number of universes.9
All is not well in contemporary science. The fundamental problems have not gone away; instead they have become more urgent. Here are some of the areas in which the hypothesis of morphic resonance points to new ways forward:
If the regularities of nature are evolving habits rather than eternal laws, there is no need to assume that all these regularities were fixed at the moment of the Big Bang. Hence there is no need to suppose that all laws of nature were intelligently designed at the moment of creation, or else that there are an infinite number of unobserved universes. These hypotheses are unnecessary if nature is radically evolutionary, as the hypothesis of formative causation proposes.Genes enable organisms to make proteins, but they do not account for the inheritance of form and behaviour. ‘Missing heritability’ is what the hypothesis of morphic resonance predicts.The idea of morphic fields with an inherent memory enables some of the central problems of molecular and developmental biology to be understood in a completely new way, which is testable experimentally.The inheritance of instincts by animals can be seen as an inheritance of habits by morphic resonance, different in degree but not in kind from individual learning.The astonishing similarities between identical twins, even when separated soon after birth, are usually assumed to be due to genetic determinism, which lies at the foundations of speculation about selfish genes. However, morphic resonance provides a simpler and completely different interpretation of the data from studies of twins.Attempts to detect long-term memory traces inside the brain have failed again and again. The idea of morphic resonance enables the brain to be seen as more like a TV receiver than a recording system. Memories are not stored in the brain: the brain tunes into them. Memory traces have proved elusive because they are not there.The hypothesis of formative causation enables the mind to be understood in terms of fields that are rooted in brains, but extend far beyond them, providing a new theory of perception and enabling many anomalous phenomena to be explained.Morphic resonance plays a major part in cultural inheritance and sheds a new light on religious practices such as rituals and the use of mantras.This hypothesis points to a new understanding of evolution as an interplay of habit and creativity, and suggests new ways of thinking about the ongoing creative processes of nature.In the Introduction I summarize this hypothesis, and outline the plan of this book.
London
January 2011
Acknowledgements
In the continued development and testing of the hypothesis of formative causation since the first edition of this book was published, many people have helped me through discussions, comments, suggestions and criticisms. In particular I would like to thank Ralph Abraham, David Abram, Patrick Bateson, Marc Bekoff, Dick Bierman, Stephen Braude, John Brockman, David Jay Brown, Bernard Carr, Christopher Clarke, Stephen Cohen, Paul Davies, Hans-Peter Dürr, Lindy Dufferin and Ava, Ted Dace, Larry Dossey, Suitbert Ertel, Susan Fassberg, Addison Fischer, David Fontana, Matthew Fox, Adele Getty, the late Edward Goldsmith, Jane Goodall, the late Brian Goodwin, Franz-Theo Gottwald, the late Stephen Jay Gould, David R. Griffin, the late Bede Griffiths, Stephan Harding, the late Willis Harman, Donald D. Hoffman, Kurt Hoffman, Nicholas Humphrey, Francis Huxley, Rick Ingrasci, Jürgen Krönig, Satish Kumar, David Lambert, David Lorimer, Katinka Matson, the late Terence McKenna, the late John Michell, the late Brendan O’Reagan, Jill Purce, Dean Radin, Anthony Ramsay, Martin Rees, Keith Roberts, Steve Rooke, Steven Rose, Janis Rozé, Alexander Shulgin, Edward St Aubyn, Gary Schwartz, Martin Schwartz, Merlin Sheldrake, the late Ian Stevenson, E. Harris Stone, James Trifone, Patrice van Eersel, the late Francisco Varela, Ian Watson and Götz Wittneben.
I am grateful to Matthew Clapp, who started my web site, www.sheldrake.org, in 1997 and served as webmaster until 2002; to my current webmaster, John Caton, who has looked after my site since 2002; and to Helmut Lasarcyk, my German webmaster, who has also kindly translated many letters, articles and manuscripts for me. I also thank my research assistant, Pam Smart, who has worked with me since 1994 and has helped in many ways.
I gratefully acknowledge organizational and financial support for research from the Institute of Noetic Sciences, California; the International Center for Integral Studies, New York; the Schweisfurth Foundation, Germany; the Lifebridge Foundation, New York; the Bial Foundation, Portugal; the Fred Foundation, Holland; the Perrott-Warrick Fund, administered by Trinity College, Cambridge; and the Watson Family Foundation. I am also grateful to the following benefactors for their generous support: the late Laurance Rockefeller; Robert L. Schwartz, of New York; the late C.W. (‘Ben’) Webster, of Toronto; Evelyn Hancock, of Old Greenwich, Connecticut; Bokhara Legendre, of Medway, South Carolina; Fred Matser, of Hilversum, Holland; Ben Finn, of London; and Addison Fischer, of Naples, Florida.
I thank Keith Roberts, Jeni Fox and Craig Robson for doing the diagrams and drawings.
The writing and rewriting of this book has involved a long journey of exploration. My companion throughout has been my wife, Jill Purce, and I am deeply thankful to her for her unfailing inspiration and encouragement, for countless conversations in which ideas in this book took shape, and for the help she has given me in so many ways.
Introduction
The habits of nature
They say that habit is second nature. Who knows but nature is only first habit?
Blaise Pascal (1623–62),Pensées
This book explores the possibility that memory is inherent in nature. It suggests that natural systems, such as termite colonies, or pigeons, or orchid plants, or insulin molecules, inherit a collective memory from all previous things of their kind, however far away they were and however long ago they existed. Because of this cumulative memory, through repetition the nature of things becomes increasingly habitual. Things are as they are because they were as they were.
Habits may be inherent in the nature of all living organisms, in crystals, molecules and atoms, and indeed in the entire cosmos. A beech seedling, for example, as it grows into a tree takes up the characteristic shape, structure, and habits of a beech. It is able to do so because it inherits its nature from previous beeches; but this inheritance is not just a matter of chemical genes. It depends also on the transmission of habits of growth and development from countless beech trees that existed in the past.
Likewise, as a swallow grows up it flies, feeds, preens, migrates, mates, and nests as swallows habitually do. It inherits the instincts of its species through invisible influences that make the behaviour of past swallows in some sense present within it. It draws on and is shaped by the collective memory of its species.
All humans too draw upon a collective memory, to which all in turn contribute.
If this view of nature is even approximately correct, it should be possible to observe the progressive establishment of new habits as they spread within a species. For example, when people learn something new, such as wind-surfing, then as more people learn to do it, it should tend to become progressively easier to learn, just because so many other people have learned to do it already. When crystals of a newly synthesized chemical substance, for example a new kind of drug, arise for the first time they have no exact precedent; but as the same compound is crystallized again and again, the crystals should tend to form more readily all over the world, just because they have already formed somewhere else.
In the same way that this inheritance of habits may depend on direct influences from previous similar things in the past, so the memory of individual organisms may depend on direct influences from their own past. If memory is inherent in the nature of things, then the inheritance of collective habits and the development of individual habits can be seen as different aspects of the same fundamental process; the process whereby the past becomes present on the basis of similarity.
Thus, our own personal habits may depend on cumulative influences from our past behaviour to which we ‘tune in’. If so, there is no need for them to be stored in a material form within our nervous systems. The same applies to our conscious memories – of a song we know, or of something that happened last year. The past may become present to us directly. Our memories may not be stored inside our brains, as we usually assume they are.
All these possibilities can be conceived of in the framework of the hypothesis of formative causation. According to this hypothesis, the nature of things depends on fields, called morphic fields. Each kind of natural system has its own kind of field: there is an insulin field, a beech field, a swallow field and so on. Such fields shape all the different kinds of atoms, molecules, crystals, living organisms, societies, customs and habits of mind.
Morphic fields, like the known fields of physics, are non-material regions of influence extending in space and continuing in time. They are localized within and around the systems they organize. When any particular organized system ceases to exist – as when an atom splits, a snowflake melts, an animal dies – its organizing field disappears from that place. But in another sense, morphic fields do not disappear: they are potential organizing patterns of influence, and can appear again physically in other times and places, wherever and whenever the physical conditions are appropriate. When they do so they contain within themselves a memory of their previous physical existences.
The process by which the past becomes present within morphic fields is called morphic resonance. Morphic resonance involves the transmission of formative causal influences through both space and time. The memory within the morphic fields is cumulative, and that is why all sorts of things become increasingly habitual through repetition. When such repetition has occurred on an astronomical scale over billions of years, as it has in the case of many kinds of atoms, molecules and crystals, the nature of these things has become so deeply habitual that it is effectively changeless, or seemingly eternal.
All this obviously contrasts with currently orthodox theories. There is no such thing in contemporary physics, chemistry or biology as morphic resonance; and the known fields of physics are assumed to be governed by eternal laws of nature. By contrast, morphic fields arise and evolve in time and space, and are influenced by what has actually happened. Morphic fields are conceived of in an evolutionary spirit, but the known fields of physics are not. Or at least, until quite recently they were not.
Until the 1960s, the universe was generally believed by physicists to be eternal; so were the properties of matter and of fields; so were the laws of nature. They always had been and always would be the same. But the universe is now thought to have been born in a primordial explosion some 14 billion years ago and to have been growing and evolving ever since.
Theoretical physics is in ferment. Theories are reaching back into the first moments of creation. Entirely new, evolutionary conceptions of matter and of fields are coming into being. The cosmos now seems more like a developing organism than an eternal machine. In this context, habits may be more natural than immutable laws.
This is the possibility that this book explores. But before beginning this exploration, it is helpful to consider in more detail the habitual assumptions we make about the nature of things. The hypothesis of formative causation conflicts with a number of scientific theories that have been orthodox for decades, or even for centuries, so it is important to be aware of what these theories are and how they have developed, and to take account of their successes and limitations.
At various stages throughout this book, the interpretations of phenomena in terms of the orthodox theories are compared with the hypothesis of formative causation. This comparison enables the alternative approaches to be understood more clearly, and it also enables us to see where they make different predictions that can be tested by experiment. By means of such tests, it should be possible to find out which approach is in better accordance with the world we live in.
The plan of this book
Any new way of thinking has to come into being in the context of existing habits of thought. The realm of science is no exception. At any given time, the generally accepted models of reality, often called paradigms, embody assumptions that are more or less taken for granted and which easily become habitual.
In the first three chapters, I examine the two predominant models of reality in contemporary science: the idea that physical reality is constant and entirely governed by eternal laws, and the idea that nature is evolutionary. In Chapter 1, I consider the way in which these two models of reality have coexisted for over a century, and how they are now in conflict as a result of the recent revolution in cosmology. All nature is now thought to be evolutionary, and consequently the assumption of eternal laws of nature is thrown into question. Rather than being governed by eternal laws, the nature of things may be habitual. This possibility was already being considered by philosophers and biologists towards the end of the nineteenth century, but it was ruled out by the orthodox assumption of an eternal physical reality.
In Chapter 2, I examine the history of the idea of the eternity of nature. It is rooted in mystical intuition, and came down to modern science through traditions of thought inherited from classical Greece. The theoretical eternities of physics have evolved from ancient, pre-evolutionary conceptions of reality, and are now at variance with evolutionary cosmology.
In Chapter 3, I look at the evolution of the idea of evolution. Its historical roots can be found in the Christian faith in the idea of the progressive movement of human history towards the fulfilment of God’s purposes. From this belief, in seventeenth-century Europe a new vision of human progress began to develop: a faith in the transformation of the world for the benefit of humanity through progress in science and technology. This conviction was continually reinforced by the advances of science, industry, medicine and agriculture, and has by now become predominant on a global scale. In the course of the nineteenth century, the progress of humanity came to be seen in a much wider context: it became one aspect of a great evolutionary process that had given rise to all forms of life on Earth. Finally, in the new cosmology the idea of evolution has been taken to its ultimate limits: the view that the whole universe is evolutionary.
As a result, we can no longer take the eternal laws of nature for granted. But if we think of them as habitual, we find ourselves in conflict with the conventional assumptions of physics, chemistry and biology, which were formulated in the context of an eternal mechanistic universe. In Chapter 4, I consider the nature of atoms, molecules, crystals, plants and animals. They are all complex structures of activity that come into being spontaneously. Why do they have the structures they do? How are they organized? How do complex living organisms such as trees develop from much simpler structures such as seeds? I look at the orthodox answers to these questions and at the assumptions they embody, and in Chapter 5 I discuss how the coming into being of living organisms – the growth of a chicken, for example, from a fertilized egg – still remains mysterious, despite the many impressive discoveries of modern biology. In contemporary biology, one of the most promising ways of thinking about the development of living organisms is in terms of organizing fields, called morphogenetic fields. However, the nature of these fields has itself remained mysterious.
In Chapter 6 I discuss the nature of these fields, and the interpretation of them provided by the hypothesis of formative causation; and in Chapter 7 I show how this hypothesis applies to the development of molecules and crystals as well as living organisms. The morphic fields of all these systems can be thought of as containing an inherent memory, due to morphic resonance from all previous similar systems.
In Chapter 8 I consider the new interpretation of biological heredity that this hypothesis provides and look at ways in which it could be tested experimentally.
Chapters 9 to 12 are concerned with memory, learning and habit in animals and human beings. The idea of morphic resonance enables memory to be understood in terms of direct causal influences from an organism’s own past. This therefore provides a radical alternative to the conventional theory that habits and memories are somehow stored as material ‘traces’ within the nervous system. This way of looking at the phenomena is unfamiliar, but it is more consistent with the available evidence than the conventional theory. It leads to a range of empirically testable predictions, and I describe some experiments that have already been done to test it.
In Chapter 13 the concept of morphic fields is extended to the organized societies of social animals, such as termite colonies and flocks of birds, and Chapter 14 considers the structures of human societies and cultures in the light of this idea. In Chapter 15, 1 suggest that the concept of morphic resonance could provide a new interpretation of rituals, customs and traditions, including the traditions of science.
The evolution of morphic fields by natural selection and the role of morphic resonance in the evolutionary process are discussed in Chapter 16, and in Chapter 17 the nature of morphic fields is considered in relation to evolutionary cosmology. Chapter 18 addresses the question of evolutionary creativity: What are the possible sources of new patterns of organization? How do new morphic fields arise in the first place?
I have tried to keep technical terminology to a minimum, but the use of some specialized scientific and philosophical terms is unavoidable. These terms are explained as the book goes along, and I hope their meanings will become clear even if they are unfamiliar to start with. There is also a glossary at the end of the book that summarizes what these words and phrases mean.
Chapter 1
Eternity and Evolution
Evolution in an eternal world
Science inherited a dual vision of the world from the nineteenth century: on the one hand a great evolutionary process on Earth, and on the other, the physical eternity of a mechanistic universe. In this vision all the matter and the energy in the cosmos were eternal, and everything was governed by eternal laws of nature.
From this dual perspective, life evolved on Earth within a physical eternity. The evolution of life made no difference to the fundamental realities of the physical universe. Nor would the extinction of life on Earth. The total amount of matter and energy and electric charge remained exactly the same, and so did all the laws of nature. Life evolved, but fundamental physical reality did not.
This double worldview has become deeply habitual, and in many ways continues to shape scientific thinking. In this chapter we examine this conventional split in more detail, and see where it has already begun to be transcended. What is emerging in its place is an evolutionary vision of reality at every level: subatomic, atomic, chemical, biological, social, ecological, cultural, mental, economic, astronomical and cosmic.
Physical eternity
The mechanical universe of nineteenth-century physics was eternal, a vast machine governed by eternal laws.
The idea of the world machine of physics started life in the seventeenth century. The machine was thought to have been made by God, set in motion by his will, and thereafter to work automatically in accordance with his immutable laws. Nevertheless, for the first century of its existence, the Newtonian world machine had a persistent tendency to run down. From time to time the celestial clockwork had to be wound up again by God.
By the beginning of the nineteenth century, the theoretical machinery had been perfected and the world became a perpetual motion machine. The machinery was eternal, and it would always go on, as it always had done, in an entirely deterministic and predictable way; or at least in a way that would in principle be predictable by a superhuman all-knowing intelligence, if such an intelligence existed.
For the great French physicist Pierre Laplace and for many subsequent scientists, God was no longer needed to wind things up or start things off. He became an unnecessary hypothesis. His universal laws remained, but no longer as ideas in his eternal mind. They had no ultimate reason for existing; they were purposeless. Everything, even physicists, became inanimate matter moving in accordance with these blind laws.
By the middle of the nineteenth century, the world machine started to run down again. It could not be a perpetual motion machine because, according to the newly formulated laws of thermodynamics, perpetual motion machines are impossible. The universe must be running down towards a final heat death, a state of thermodynamic equilibrium in which the machinery would stop working, never to start again. The machine would run out of steam, and a God who had become an unnecessary hypothesis could not be expected to stoke it up again. Nevertheless, all the matter and energy of the world would endure forever; the remnants of the exhausted machinery would never decay.
The revolutions in twentieth-century physics transcended the old mechanistic metaphors in a variety of ways.1The indestructible billiard-ball atoms became complex systems of vibrating and orbiting particles, themselves complex structures of activity. The rigorous determinism of classical mechanistic theory softened into a science of probabilities. And spontaneity re-emerged in everything. Even the vacuum ceased to be an empty void; it became a seething ocean of energy, producing countless vibrating particles all the time and taking them back again. ‘A vacuum is not inert and featureless, but alive with throbbing energy and vitality.’2
The world machine of matter in motion was transformed by relativity and quantum physics into a cosmic system of fields and energy. As Einstein conceived of it, the universe existed eternally within the universal field of gravitation. He did not conclude that the universe was essentially constant because of his general relativity theory, but in spite of it.3He adjusted his equations to endow the universe with an eternal stability:
When Einstein first applied his field equations of general relativity to the cosmological problem he discovered that static solutions were impossible. Since there was at that time no observational evidence to suggest that the Universe was in a non-static state and the philosophical prejudices of centuries underpinned the notion of a changeless background universe, Einstein altered his field equations to include the cosmological constant, L. The Einstein equations with cosmological constant have a static cosmological solution: the Einstein static universe.
John Barrow and Frank Tipler4
Static models of the universe remained orthodox until the 1960s, and many of the habits of thought engendered by the idea of a physical eternity still persist with great power.
Evolution
We also inherited from nineteenth-century science a great evolutionary vision, very different in spirit from the eternal universe of physics. The many kinds of living organisms – centipedes, dolphins, bamboos, sparrows, and millions of other species – have come into being through a vast creative process. The evolutionary tree has been growing and branching spontaneously for well over 3 billion years. We ourselves are products of evolution, and evolution continues at an ever-accelerating pace in the realm of humanity. Societies and cultures evolve, civilizations evolve, economies evolve, and science and technology evolve.
We experience the evolutionary process directly in our own lives: the world around us is changing as it has never changed before. Stretching back behind the changes that we ourselves have seen is the evolution of modern civilization, itself rooted in earlier civilizations and more primitive forms of society. Beyond these is a long, mysterious period of prehistoric humanity; further back still, our apelike ancestors; beyond them, more primitive mammals, then reptiles, then fish, then primitive vertebrates, then perhaps some sort of worm, right back to single cells, to microbes, and ultimately to the first living cells on Earth. Beyond these we go back into a chemical realm of molecules and crystals, and finally to atoms and subatomic particles. This is our evolutionary lineage.
In the course of our growing up and education, most modern people have implicitly or explicitly accepted both models of reality: a physical eternity and an evolutionary process. Within the sciences, both models coexisted peacefully until quite recently. They were kept safely apart. Evolution was kept down to earth, whereas the heavens were eternal. Evolution was the province of geology, biology and the social sciences. The celestial realm was the province of physics.
Charles Darwin and biologists who followed him had to try to fit the evolutionary tree of life into a mechanical universe that was not evolving – it was devolving. The world machine had no ultimate purpose, and no such things as purposes could be admitted within it. From the mechanistic point of view, living organisms are complex machines, inanimate and purposeless. The Darwinian doctrine is that the evolution of living organisms in no sense involves a process of purposive striving, nor is it divinely designed or guided; rather, organisms vary by chance, their offspring tend to inherit their variations, and through the blind workings of natural selection, the various forms of life evolve with no design or purpose, either conscious or unconscious. Eyes and wings, mango trees and weaver birds, ant and termite colonies, the echolocation system of bats, and all other aspects of life have come into being through the operation of inanimate forces, through blind chance and by the power of natural selection.
The Darwinian theory of evolution has always been controversial, and remains so today. Some people still deny that evolution has happened at all; others dispute that it is purposeless and depends on blind chance; and some go much further than Darwinism: they see the evolution of life on Earth as part of a universal evolutionary process.
Philosophies of universal evolution, such as the theories of progress so popular in Victorian England, conflicted with the universe according to physics. So did evolutionary visions such as that of Teilhard de Chardin,5who saw the evolutionary process being drawn towards an end or goal, an inconceivable state of final unity. From the point of view of mechanistic science, such philosophies and visions have generally been regarded as illusory: the evolution of life on Earth is not part of a cosmic evolutionary process that is leading somewhere; it is a local fluctuation within a mechanistic universe that has no purpose at all.
We are all familiar with this point of view, which had a deep and pervasive influence on twentieth-century thought. This is how the philosopher Bertrand Russell expressed it in the context of the devolving world machine:
That man is the product of causes which had no prevision of the end they were achieving; that his origin, his growth, his hopes and fears, his loves and beliefs, are but the outcome of accidental collisions of atoms; that no fire, no heroism, no intensity of thought and feeling, can preserve an individual life beyond the grave; that all the labours of the ages, all the devotion, all the inspiration, all the noonday brightness of human genius, are destined to extinction in the vast death of the solar system; and that the whole temple of Man’s achievement must inevitably be buried beneath the debris of a universe in ruins – all these things, if not quite beyond dispute, are yet so nearly certain, that no philosophy which rejects them can hope to stand. Only within the scaffolding of these truths, only on the firm foundation of unyielding despair, can the soul’s habitation henceforth be built.6
This cheerless prospect has indeed seemed inevitable to many modern people, and the replacement of the devolving world machine with an Einsteinian static universe made little difference to this pessimistic outlook. The mechanistic theory is more than just a scientific theory: it has been taken to be a dreadful truth that no rational person can deny, whatever existential anguish it may cause. In this austere faith the molecular biologist Jacques Monod proclaimed:
Man must at last wake out of his millenary dream and discover his total solitude, his fundamental isolation. He must realize that, like a gypsy, he lives on the boundary of an alien world; a world that is deaf to his music, and as indifferent to his hopes as it is to his sufferings and his crimes.7
But scientific theories are subject to change, and in the 1960s the theoretical universe of physics broke out of its eternity. It no longer looks like an eternal machine, but more like a developing organism. Everything is evolutionary. The evolution of life on Earth and the development of humanity are no longer a local fluctuation in an eternal physical reality; they are aspects of a cosmic evolutionary process. A variety of philosophers and visionaries have been saying this for years, but now this is orthodox physics as well.8
The evolutionary universe
Most cosmologists now believe that the universe began in a primordial explosion some 14 billion years ago and that it has been growing ever since. There are two possible futures. Either the universe will expand forever; or its expansion will slow down, stop, and begin to contract, ultimately resulting in a reversal of the Big Bang in a terminal implosion called the Big Crunch. Fashions change fast in cosmology, and the shifting theories depend on the estimated amounts of dark matter and dark energy that the universe contains. The nature of both is literally obscure. Dark matter contributes to the gravitational pull that slows down the universal expansion, while dark energy pushes the universe apart, increasing its rate of expansion. In 2010, the best estimate was that regular matter made up less than 5 per cent of the universe, with dark matter accounting for 23 per cent and dark energy 72 per cent. Most physicists seem to favour continued expansion; but some prefer the Big Crunch, and see in it a way to return to a repetitive eternity: for the Big Crunch could be the Big Bang of the next universe, and so on forever.
However, even if we assume for the purpose of argument that our universe is one in an endless series, we could never know whether they all develop in exactly the same way or evolve differently each time. All we can know about is the evolution of the universe we live in.
Opinions differ as to what happened in the first 10–30seconds, but according to the ‘inflationary’ model, the universe had a very brief period of extraordinarily rapid expansion during which all the matter and energy in the universe were created from virtually nothing.9After this, the inflationary model coincides with what is now called the ‘standard’ Big Bang model.
About a hundredth of a second after the beginning, when the universe had cooled to 100 billion degrees, it consisted of an undifferentiated soup of matter and radiation. Within three minutes, the neutrons and protons began to combine into helium nuclei. Within 30 minutes, most of them were combined in this way, or remained as free protons, hydrogen nuclei.10
After a further 700,000 years of expansion and cooling, the temperature dropped low enough that electrons and nuclei could form stable atoms. The lack of free electrons then made the universe transparent to radiation, and the ‘decoupling’ of matter and radiation allowed galaxies and stars to begin to form.
The evolution of matter continued within the stars, where nuclear reactions produced the many chemical elements that are found in dust clouds between the stars, in comets, meteors and planets. Such elements are thought to be formed with particular intensity when stars explode as supernovae. In the cold conditions of interstellar space the formation of molecules becomes possible; and in cool aggregates of matter, for instance planets, a great variety of crystals come into being, such as those that make up the rocks of the Earth.
In this sequence, the one, the primordial ‘singularity’, becomes many, as ever more complex forms differentiate within the universe as it grows.
This image is far removed from the constant mechanical universe of classical physics. The evolutionary conception is now being extended to everything, even to the fundamental particles and fields of physics. Here is a description by Paul Davies, a theoretical physicist:
In the beginning the universe was a featureless ferment of quantum energy, a state of exceptionally high symmetry. Indeed, the initial state of the universe could well have been the simplest possible. It was only as the universe rapidly expanded and cooled that the familiar structures in the world ‘froze out’ of the primeval furnace. One by one the four fundamental forces separated out from the superforce. Step by step the particles which go to build all the matter in the world acquired their present identities … One might say that the highly ordered and intricate cosmos we see today ‘congealed’ from the structureless uniformity of the big bang. All the fundamental structure around us is a relic or fossil from that initial phase. The more primitive the object, the earlier the epoch at which it was forged in the primeval furnace.11
The universe would have developed very differently if the laws and constants of physics had been even slightly different. There is noa priorireason known to physics why they should be as they are. Yet they are as they are, and so life on Earth and we ourselves have been able to evolve. The laws of physics have to take into account the fact that physicists exist. This consideration is essential to modern cosmology, and is expressed in the Anthropic Cosmological Principle. The ‘weak form’ of this principle is now widely accepted:12‘The observed values of all physical and cosmological quantities are not equally probable, but they take on values restricted by the requirement that there exist sites where carbon-based life can evolve and by the requirement that the Universe be old enough for it to have already done so.’13
Some physicists go further in advocating a ‘strong form’ of the anthropic principle: ‘The Universe must have those properties which allow life to develop within it at some stage in its history.’14
At first sight this seems tautological, a rather ponderous restatement of an obvious truth. Nevertheless it is intensely controversial because of its implication that the universe may, after all, have a grand purpose and design. Some cosmologists go even further:
Suppose that for some unknown reason the Strong Anthropic Principle is true and that intelligent life must come into existence at some stage in the Universe’s history. But if it dies out at our stage of development, long before it has had any measurable non-quantum influence on the Universe in the large, it is hard to see why it must have come into existence in the first place. This motivates the following generalization of the Strong Anthropic Principle:Final Anthropic Principle: Intelligent information-processing must come into existence in the Universe, and, once it comes into existence, it will never die out.15
For atheists and materialists, the idea of a universe designed in such a way that life and intelligence are likely to emerge has disturbing theological implications. But there is an easy way out, which has become increasingly popular since the turn of the millennium: the multiverse theory. Our universe could be just one of a vast number, perhaps even an infinity, of parallel universes, each with different laws and constants. Then there would be no problem about our universe being fine-tuned in exactly the right way for us to emerge within it, because we just happen to be in the right one for us. As the cosmologist Bernard Carr has expressed it: ‘Since we necessarily reside in one of the life-conducive universes, the multiverse picture reduces the strong anthropic principle to an aspect of the weak one. For this reason, many physicists would regard the multiverse proposal as providing the most natural explanation of the anthropic fine tunings.’16In order to get rid of a God who fine-tuned the universe when it first came into being, many scientists are prepared to accept the existence of an infinity of parallel universes, for which there is no empirical evidence whatsoever. Some try to justify this move in terms of Occam’s razor, the principle of parsimonious explanation proposed by William of Occam, a fourteenth-century Franciscan friar: ‘Plurality should not be posited without necessity,’ or ‘Entities should not be multiplied beyond necessity.’
Multiplying entire universes without limit seems like the ultimate violation of Occam’s razor. But even this extravagant speculation cannot settle the matter:
Since within the world’s theistic traditions, God is considered infinite and infinitely creative, it makes sense that creation would reflect these attributes, and hence that physical reality might be much larger than one universe. Further it makes sense that an infinitely creative God might create these universes via some sort of universe-generator, since arguably this would be more elegant and ingenious than just creating themex nihilo[out of nothing].
Robin Collins17
The very existence of such debates among contemporary physicists and philosophers shows how far modern cosmology has moved beyond the double worldview that has been orthodox for so many years. For generations of scientists, physical eternity seemed to be the basis of all reality. But this was not an absolute scientific truth, even though it was often regarded as such; it was just a theory – a theory that has now been superseded by physics itself. Whether the cosmic evolutionary process results from divine creativity or not, whether it has any purpose or not, and whether there are innumerable universes or not, according to the new cosmology, we live within an evolving universe.
Do the laws of nature evolve?
These evidence-free discussions about a universe fine-tuned by God, or a multiverse without a God, or a God of the multiverse, all share a common assumption: that the laws and constants of nature were all fixed from the outset. But as Terence McKenna remarked: ‘Modern science is based on the principle: “Give us one free miracle and we’ll explain the rest.” The one free miracle is the appearance of all the mass and energy in the universe and all the laws that govern it from nothing in a single instant.’18
The standard assumption is that physical reality evolves while the laws of nature stay the same. But why should we assume that all the laws of nature were already present at the instant of the Big Bang, like a cosmic Napoleonic code? The pre-existence of these laws cannot possibly be tested before the emergence of the phenomena they govern. In an evolutionary universe, perhaps the laws of nature evolve along with nature.
In any case, what do we mean by the ‘laws of nature’?
Water boils in the same way in Scotland, Thailand and New Guinea, and everywhere else too. Under given conditions it boils at predictable temperatures – 100°C at standard atmospheric pressure. Sugar crystals form in much the same way under similar conditions all over the world. Chick embryos develop in much the same way everywhere when fertilized hens’ eggs are incubated under appropriate conditions. We usually assume that all these things happen because the appropriate materials, given the appropriate physical and chemical conditions, are under the influence of natural laws – laws that are invisible and intangible, but are nevertheless present everywhere and always. There is order in nature; and the order depends on law.
These hypothetical laws of nature are somehow independent of the things they govern. For example, the laws governing the formation of sugar crystals do not operate only inside and around the growing crystals, but also exist outside them. They have an existence that transcends particular times and places. Thus the sugar crystals that are forming today in sugar factories in Cuba are not following local Cuban laws, but rather laws of nature which apply everywhere on Earth, and indeed everywhere in the universe. These laws of nature cannot be altered by any laws the government of Cuba may pass, and they are not affected by what people think – not even by what scientists think. Sugar crystals formed perfectly well (as far as we know) before the structure of sugar molecules was worked out by organic chemists and before the structure of their crystals was worked out by crystallographers; indeed these crystals were forming perfectly well before were any scientists at all. The laws have an objective existence quite independent of human beings, and even independent of the existence of the crystals themselves. They are eternal. They existed before the first sugar molecules arose anywhere in the universe. They have existed since the Big Bang, and they may have existed before there was a universe at all, as eternal realities which transcend time and space.
But wait a minute. How could we possiblyknowthat the laws of nature existed before the universe came into being? Or that they all appeared at the instant of the Big Bang? We could not ever hope to prove it by experiment. This is surely no more than a metaphysical assumption. Nevertheless, this assumption is still taken for granted by most scientists, including evolutionary cosmologists. This assumption became habitual when physical reality was thought to be eternal, and has persisted in spite of the revolution in cosmology. But then where or what were the laws of nature before the Big Bang?
The nothingness ‘before’ the creation of the universe is the most complete void that we can imagine – no space, time or matter existed. It is a world without place, without duration or eternity, without number – it is what mathematicians call ‘the empty set’. Yet this unthinkable void converts itself into a plenum of existence – a necessary consequence of physical laws. Where are these laws written into that void? What ‘tells’ the void that it is pregnant with a possible universe? It would seem that even the void is subject to law, a logic that exists prior to time and space.19
This assumption that the laws of nature are eternal is the last great surviving legacy of the old cosmology. We are rarely even conscious of making it. But when we do bring this assumption into awareness, we can see that it is only one of several possibilities. Perhaps all the laws of nature came into being at the very moment of the Big Bang. Or perhaps they arose in stages, and then, having arisen, persisted changelessly thereafter. For example, the laws governing the crystallization of sugar may have come into being when sugar molecules first crystallized somewhere in the universe; they may have been universal and changeless ever since. Or perhaps the laws of nature evolved along with nature herself. Perhaps they are still evolving. Or perhaps they are not laws at all, but more like habits. Maybe the very idea of ‘laws’ is inappropriate.
The concept of laws of nature is metaphorical. It is based on an analogy with human laws, which are binding rules of conduct prescribed by authority and extending throughout the realm of the sovereign power. In the seventeenth century, the metaphor was quite explicit: the laws of nature were framed by God, the lord of the universe. His laws were immutable; his writ ran everywhere and always. Through his omnipotence, God was also the universal law enforcement agency.
Although many people no longer believe in such a God, his changeless laws have survived him to this day. But when we pause to consider the nature of these laws, they rapidly become mysterious. They govern matter and motion, but they are not themselves material nor do they move. They cannot be seen or weighed or touched; they lie beyond the realm of sense experience. They are potentially present everywhere and always. They have no physical source or origin. Indeed, even in the absence of God, they still share many of his traditional attributes. They are omnipresent, immutable, universal and self-subsistent. Nothing can be hidden from them, nor lie beyond their power.
Eternal laws made sense when they were ideas within the mind of God, as they were for the founding fathers of modern science. They still seemed to make sense when they governed an eternal universe from which God’s mind had been dissolved. But do they any longer make sense in the context of the Big Bang and an evolving universe?
When we look again at the source of the legal metaphor, human legal systems, we see at once that real laws do indeed develop and evolve. In the English tradition, the common law that governs so much of our lives has grown up over many centuries, rooted in ancestral customs and judicial precedents, continually developing as circumstances change and as new situations arise. And in all countries, new laws are enacted and old ones modified or repealed by the powers that be. Constitutional governments are themselves subject to legal constitutions, which likewise change and evolve. From time to time, old constitutions are overturned by revolutions and replaced by new ones, drawn up by constitution-makers. We apply this idea to science itself in the metaphor of scientific revolutions. They establish new scientific constitutions, within which new scientific laws are framed.
If we are to persist with the legal metaphor, it might be appropriate to suppose that the evolving natural world is governed by a system of natural common law, rather than by a preformed legal system established at the outset.
But then who or what corresponds to the judicial system that establishes the precedents? And who or what framed the constitution of the Big Bang in the first place? And by what power or authority are they maintained? These questions arise inevitably, because they are implicit in the metaphor of law. Laws imply lawgivers, and they are maintained by the power of the government. If we drop the idea that the laws of nature are framed and maintained by God, then we must ask: what makes them up and how are they sustained?
Many philosophers would deny that these questions have any meaning. From the point of view of the empiricist tradition, what we call the laws of nature are in fact human concepts that merely refer to regularities which scientists observe, describe and model. They have no real, objective existence. They are theories and hypotheses in human minds.20