13,99 €
The time of the landscape is not the time when people started describing gardens, mountains and lakes in poems or representing them in works of art: it is the time when the landscape imposed itself as a specific object of thought. It is the time when both the harmony of arranged gardens and the disharmony of wild nature led to a revolution in the criteria of the beautiful and in the meaning of the word "art." It coincided with the birth of aesthetics, understood as a regime for shaping how art is seen and thought, and also with the French Revolution, understood as a revolution in the very idea of what binds together a human community. The time of the landscape is the time when the conjunction of these two upheavals brought into focus, however hazily, a common horizon: that of a revolution that no longer concerns only the laws of the state or the norms of art, but the very forms of sensible experience. This brilliant and wide-ranging book will be of interest to students and scholars in philosophy, literature, the visual arts, and the humanities generally, and to anyone interested in critical theory and philosophy.
Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:
Seitenzahl: 150
Cover
Dedication
Title Page
Copyright
Abbreviations
Foreword
Notes
I. A Newcomer to the Fine Arts
Notes
II. Scenes of Nature
Notes
III. The Landscape as Painting
Notes
IV. Beyond the Visible
Notes
V. Politics of the Landscape
Notes
Epilogue
Notes
Ebook plates
End User License Agreement
Cover
Table of Contents
Dedication
Title Page
Copyright
Abbreviations
Foreword
Begin Reading
Epilogue
Ebook plates
End User License Agreement
ii
iii
iv
vii
viii
ix
x
xi
xii
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
102
To the memory of my mother.J. R.
Jacques Rancière
Translated by Emiliano Battista
polity
Originally published in French as Le temps du paysage: Aux origines de la révolution esthétique © La Fabrique Editions, 2017
This English edition © Polity Press, 2023
This book is supported by the Institut français (Royaume-Uni) as part of the Burgess programme.
Polity Press65 Bridge StreetCambridge CB2 1UR, UK
Polity Press111 River StreetHoboken, NJ 07030, USA
All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purpose of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher.
ISBN-13: 978-1-5095-4816-3
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Control Number: 2022937839
The publisher has used its best endeavors to ensure that the URLs for external websites referred to in this book are correct and active at the time of going to press. However, the publisher has no responsibility for the websites and can make no guarantee that a site will remain live or that the content is or will remain appropriate.
Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition.
For further information on Polity, visit our website: politybooks.com
Burke (1757)
Burke, Edmund.
A Philosophical Enquiry into the Origin of Our Ideas of the Sublime and Beautiful
, ed. Adam Phillips. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 1990.
Burke (1790)
Burke, Edmund.
Reflections on the Revolution in France
, ed. Frank M. Turner. New Haven and London: Yale University Press, 2003.
De Luc (1778)
De Luc, Jean-André.
Lettres physiques et morales sur les montagnes et sur l’histoire de la terre et de l’homme
. The Hague: Detune, 1778.
Gilpin (1772)
Gilpin, William.
Observations, Relative Chiefly to Picturesque Beauty, Made in the Year 1772, on Several Parts of England; Particularly the Mountains, and Lakes of Cumberland
,
and Westmoreland
, 2 vols. London: R. Blamire, 1792 [1786].
Gilpin (1776)
Gilpin, William.
Observations, Relative Chiefly to Picturesque Beauty, Made in the Year 1776, on Several Parts of Great Britain; Particularly the High-Lands of Scotland
, 2 vols. London: R. Blamire, 1792 [1789].
Hegel (1835)
Hegel, G. W. F.
Aesthetics: Lectures on Fine Art
, 2 vols. Trans. T. M. Knox. Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1988.
Kant (1790)
Kant, Immanuel.
Critique of Judgment
. Trans. James Creed Meredith, revised by Nicholas Walker. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2007.
Knight (1794)
Knight, Richard Payne.
Landscape: A
Didactic Poem
. London: W. Bulmer and Co., 1794.
Price (1794)
Price, Uvedale.
An Essay on the
Picturesque, as Compared with the Sublime and the Beautiful; And, on the Use of Studying Pictures, for the Purposes of Improving Real Landscape
. London: J. Robson, 1794.
Price (1810)
Price, Uvedale.
Essays on the Picturesque, as Compared with the Sublime and the Beautiful; And, on the Use of Studying Pictures, for the Purposes of Improving
Real Landscape
, 3 vols. London: J. Mawman, 1810.
Whately (1770)
Whately, Thomas.
Observations on Modern Gardening, Illustrated by Descriptions
. London: T. Payne, 1770.
I should specify the object that gives this book its title. The time of the landscape discussed here is not the time when flowery gardens, majestic mountains, peaceful lakes, or rough and choppy seas started being described in poems or depicted on walls. It is the time when the landscape imposed itself as a specific object of thought. This object of thought was constituted through quarrels about how gardens should be designed, descriptions of parks adorned by classical temples or humble country lanes, narratives of journeys to solitary lakes and mountains, and evocations of mythological or rustic paintings. This book, then, will follow the specific twists and turns of these narratives and quarrels. What they gave rise to is not so much the taste for a spectacle that delights the eyes or elevates the soul, but the experience of a form of unity in sensible diversity capable of changing the configuration of modes of perception and objects of thought that had existed until then. The time of the landscape is the time when the harmony of landscaped gardens, or the disharmony of wild nature, led to an upheaval in the criterion of the beautiful, and even in the meaning of the word “art.” That upheaval entailed another, which affected a notion that is as fundamental in common usage as in philosophical reflection: nature. Whatever impacts nature impacts also the society that is supposed to obey its laws. And so the time of the landscape is also the time when the felicitous organization of society borrowed its metaphors from the harmony of fields, forests, and streams.
In Western societies, it is possible to situate this time quite precisely. It coincides with the birth of aesthetics, understood not as a particular discipline but as a regime for how art is seen and thought. It is also contemporary with the French Revolution, understood not as a succession of more or less violent institutional upheavals, but as a revolution in the very idea of what binds a human community together. And it is also the time when the conjunction of these two upheavals brought a common horizon, however hazily, into focus: that of a revolution that is no longer concerned solely with the laws of the state or the norms of art, but with the very forms of sensible experience. This revolution has been at the center of my work for a long time, and is notably at the heart of a book I published in 2011 entitled Aisthesis: Scenes from the Aesthetic Regime of Art. That book collects fourteen telling scenes, ranging from the evocation of an ancient statue in ruins in the 1760s to the description of the interiors of the barracks inhabited by poor sharecroppers in the 1930s. I had already indicated there that this list could be expanded, and the present volume can be seen as such an expansion: yet another scene capable of bringing into view the genesis and transformations of a regime of art, and of the common sensible world it outlines. Moreover, “the time of the landscape” fits quite naturally into the network of artistic and political temporalities that I tried to sketch out in Modern Times.1
1.
Cf.
Aisthesis: Scenes from the Aesthetic Regime of Art
, trans. Zakir Paul (London and New York: Verso, 2013), and
Modern Times: Temporality in Art and Politics
, trans. Gregory Elliot (New York: Verso, 2022).
Painting, as the second kind of formative art, which presents sensible appearance in artful combination with ideas, I would divide into that of the beautiful depiction of nature, and that of the beautiful arrangement of its products. The first is painting proper, the second landscape gardening.1
That is how Kant introduced a newcomer to the classification of the fine arts in 1790: the art of “landscape gardening,” which consists in the “beautiful arrangement” of the “products” of nature. In so doing, Kant was confirming something that a few seminal works from the period had already recognized. Thomas Whately published his Observations on Modern Gardening in London in 1770, and a French translation appeared the following year. In 1779, Christian Cay Lorenz Hirschfeld’s five-volume Theorie der Gartenkunst appeared simultaneously in German and French.2 In 1782, Jacques Delille put the new theories into verse in Les Jardins, a poem in four cantos that enjoyed considerable success at the time.3 It was Whately, in fact, who defined the art of landscape gardening as the art of arranging the products of nature in the most perfect manner. And it was also Whately who, in the opening sentence of his Introduction, proclaimed the recent consecration of this art: “Gardening, in the perfection to which it has lately been brought in England, is entitled to a place of considerable rank among the liberal arts.”4
The question, then, is to know what accounts for this novelty and perfection. The claim would certainly have surprised connoisseurs. Books about the art of landscape gardening had by then been circulating for two centuries already. Some among them had proclaimed its ancient lineage by evoking the orchards of Alcinous (in Book Seven of the Odyssey), the mythical hanging gardens of Babylon, and the painted Roman villas described in two often-cited letters by Pliny the Younger. Closer to Whately’s time, the Garden of Venus celebrated in The Dream of Poliphilus5 and the Garden of Eden sung by Milton had captured many an imagination, and the culture of Italian literati had inspired the sophisticated architecture of symbolic gardens. Poets and travelers in the seventeenth century had admired the wonders that Salomon de Caus built for the Elector Palatinate in Heidelberg, and that Le Nôtre designed for the French king at Versailles. The arrangement of embroidered parterres (parterres en broderie), green rooms (cabinets de verdure), bowling-greens, porticos, or labyrinths had been formalized and abundantly illustrated since 1629, when Daniel Loris published Le Thrésor des parterres in Geneva. Indeed, the art of gardening seemed already to be celebrating its perfection in 1709, when Dezallier d’Argenville published La Théorie et la pratique du jardinage, an encyclopedic work whose full title promises “new designs of parterres, groves, grass-plots, mazes, banqueting rooms, galleries, porticos, terraces, stairs, fountains, cascades,” as well as the “manner of making the ground, forming designs suitable to the place, and putting them in execution, according to the principles of geometry,” and the “method of setting and raising in little time, all the plants requisite in fine gardens: also the way to find water, to convey it into gardens, and to make basons and fountains for the same. Together with remarks and general rules in all that concerns the art of gardening.”6 We might conclude that the perfection attained there belies the novelty that Whately claimed seventy years later. That conclusion, however, would hide the core of the problem, which turns precisely on knowing what is to be understood by “art” and “perfection.” The fact is that, although Dezallier d’Argenville promised innumerable marvels, he was not at all interested in getting the fine arts to welcome into its ranks the art of Le Nôtre and his emulators. On the contrary, it was just at the moment when this science of parterres, bowling-greens, labyrinths, canals, and porticos had fallen into discredit that Whately – and Kant after him – claimed this dignity for it.
This seeming paradox teaches an essential lesson: the dignity of an art is something other than its formal perfection. In general, what we call art is the skill (savoir-faire) that a will deploys in order to give matter a form. The ingenuity of the conception and the virtuosity of its execution are one way to recognize the perfection acquired in the exercise of a skill. But that is not the same as knowing what objects they produce, and to what end. Traditionally, the excellence of an art had been defined solely in relation to the latter; indeed, that is how the liberal arts had distinguished themselves from the mechanical arts. The latter produced objects that served the needs of human beings, while the former provided pleasure to those whose spheres of existence extended beyond the simple circle of needs. In order to become a liberal art, the art of gardening had to do more than just increase the amount of science that went into its creations. It had to separate its ends from the two needs – the medicinal and the alimentary – usually associated with the cultivation of plants. It was easy for the art of gardening to distance itself both from the traditional collection of medicinal plants, and from the vegetable garden, whose products were destined for the kitchen. For a long time, though, the art of gardening kept its links to the orchard, where the useful was closely tied to the agreeable. Recent studies have pointed out that the famous gardens of the Villa Lante, in Bagnaia, which served as archetypes for Renaissance gardens in Italy, were sites for the intense cultivation of fruit.7 John Parkinson, for his part, reminded readers of his Paradisi in Sole. Paradisus Terrestris, published in London in 1629, that the plants of the Garden of Eden were not just meant to satisfy hunger, but to please the eyes. On the book’s frontispiece, vines, apple trees, pineapples, and date palms are combined with tulips, carnations, cyclamen, and fritillaries to convey the image of an earthly paradise.
The architectural magnificence of Le Nôtre’s gardens cut the knot that bound the art of vistas and embroidered parterres to the cultivation of fruit trees. Still, the distance that Le Nôtre established between his art and utility proved to be no more efficient than the perfection of garden designs in gaining for the art of gardening a place among the liberal arts. That is because the excellence that separated the liberal from the mechanical arts could not be measured solely through the pleasure that the talent of the architect provided to members of the very upper classes. In the course of the eighteenth century, the liberal arts had taken on a new name: the fine arts. For an art to gain the title of fine art, it had to do more than provide refined pleasure to the well born. It had to satisfy an autonomous criterion of beauty by producing a specific pleasure rooted in the imitation of nature. “Nature – that is, all of reality plus all that we can readily conceive to be possible – is the prototype or model for the arts.”8 So writes Batteux in The Fine Arts Reduced to the Same Principle, a book that was still considered an authority in Kant’s time. For Batteux, the word nature does not evoke images of greenery. Rather, to have nature as a model meant two things: to imitate the traits presented by the objects and beings of nature so as to make them recognizable while also rendering them more beautiful; and to imitate – by assembling the visible traits of nature – an invisible nature defined as the perfect combination of its elements into a coherent whole.
For the art of gardening to be elevated to the rank of fine art, it had to do more than simply separate itself from every useful end. It also had to satisfy the criterion through which beautiful works are recognized. In other words, it had to imitate nature – or, rather, “beautiful nature,” which is not satisfied with reproducing the traits that render things recognizable, but goes further and assembles the traits, borrowed from the most beautiful models, into a perfect figure that is not to be found in simple nature. This principle is illustrated by the example, so oft-repeated, of Zeuxis, who availed himself of the traits of five different women in order to compose the ideal image of Helen. That is what the “beautiful arrangement” of nature’s “products” had to do: not just transform nature, but imitate it by composing, on the ground itself and using the sparse beauties it dispenses, a superior beauty. A problem emerges, however, when the word nature also starts to mean rolling hills and valleys, green trees and meadows, and trickling streams: how can one imitate nature by using its products? After all, to imitate nature had meant to reproduce its traits in objects that are not natural. Batteux had been quite explicit on this point: unlike the mechanical arts, the fine arts do not use nature, they only imitate it. The products of the fine arts are not just different from nature, they are its exact opposite: artificial beings. How, then, can the art of gardening – the art that imitates nature with nature’s own products – gain entrance without contradiction into the kingdom of the fine arts, given that it breaks one of the fundamental principles of the fine arts?