This book contains a selection from my writings on Art
extending over a period of twenty years. Some essays have never
before been published in England; and I have also added a good deal
of new matter and made slight corrections throughout. In the
laborious work of hunting up lost and forgotten publications, and
in the work of selection, revision, and arrangement I owe
everything to Mr. R. R. Tatlock’s devoted and patient
labour.
WHEN we look at ancient works of art we habitually treat them
not merely as objects of æsthetic enjoyment but also as successive
deposits of the human imagination. It is indeed this view of works
of art as crystallised history that accounts for much of the
interest felt in ancient art by those who have but little æsthetic
feeling and who find nothing to interest them in the work of their
contemporaries where the historical motive is lacking and they are
left face to face with bare æsthetic values.I once knew an old gentleman who had retired from his city
office to a country house—a fussy, feeble little being who had cut
no great figure in life. He had built himself a house which was
preternaturally hideous; his taste was deplorable and his manners
indifferent; but he had a dream, the dream of himself as an
exquisite and refined intellectual dandy living in a society of
elegant frivolity. To realise this dream he had spent large sums in
buying up every scrap of eighteenth-century French furniture which
he could lay hands on. These he stored in an immense upper floor in
his house which was always locked except when he went up to indulge
in his dream and to become for a time a courtier at Versailles
doing homage to the du Barry, whose toilet-tables and what-nots
were strewn pell-mell about the room without order or effect of any
kind. Such is an extreme instance of the historical way of looking
at works of art. For this old gentleman, as for how many an
American millionaire, art was merely a help to an imagined dream
life.To many people then it seems an easy thing to pass thus
directly from the work of art to the life of the time which
produced it. We all in fact weave an imagined Middle Ages around
the parish church and an imagined Renaissance haunts us in the
college courts of Oxford and Cambridge. We don’t, I fancy, stop to
consider very closely how true the imagined life is: we are
satisfied with the prospect of another sort of life which we might
have lived, which we often think we might have preferred to our
actual life. We don’t stop to consider much how far the pictured
past corresponds to any reality, certainly not to consider what
proportion of the whole reality of the past life gets itself
embalmed in this way in works of art. Thus we picture our Middle
Ages as almost entirely occupied with religion and war, our
Renaissance as occupied in learning, and our eighteenth century as
occupied in gallantry and wit. Whereas, as a matter of fact, all of
these things were going on all the time while the art of each
period has for some reason been mainly taken up with the expression
of one or another activity. There is indeed a certain danger in
accepting too naïvely the general atmosphere—the ethos, which the
works of art of a period exhale. Thus when we look at the
thirteenth-century sculpture of Chartres or Beauvais we feel at
once the expression of a peculiar gracious piety, a smiling and gay
devoutness which we are tempted to take for the prevailing mood of
the time—and which we perhaps associate with the revelation of just
such a type of character in S. Francis of Assisi. A study of
Salimbeni’s chronicle with its interminable record of squalid
avarice and meanness, or of the fierce brutalities of Dante’s
Inferno are necessary correctives of such a pleasant
dream.It would seem then that the correspondence between art and
life which we so habitually assume is not at all constant and
requires much correction before it can be trusted. Let us approach
the same question from another point and see what result we obtain.
Let us consider the great revolutions in art and the revolutions in
life and see if they coincide. And here let me try to say what I
mean by life as contrasted with art. I mean the general
intellectual and instinctive reaction to their surroundings of
those men of any period whose lives rise to complete
self-consciousness. Their view of the universe as a whole and their
conception of their relations to their kind. Of course their
conception of the nature and function of art will itself be one of
the most varying aspects of life and may in any particular period
profoundly modify the correspondence of art to life.Perhaps the greatest revolution in life that we know of at
all intimately was that which effected the change from Paganism to
Christianity. That this was no mere accident is evident from the
fact that Christianity was only one of many competing religions,
all of which represented a closely similar direction of thought and
feeling. Any one of these would have produced practically the same
effect, that of focussing men’s minds on the spiritual life as
opposed to the material life which had pre-occupied them for so
long. One cannot doubt then that here was a change which denoted a
long prepared and inevitable readjustment of men’s attitude to
their universe. Now the art of the Roman Empire showed no trace
whatever of this influence; it went on with precisely the same
motives and principles which had satisfied Paganism. The subjects
changed and became mainly Christian, but the treatment was so
exactly similar that it requires more than a cursory glance to say
if the figure on a sarcophagus is Christ or Orpheus, Moses or
Æsculapius.The next great turning-point in history is that which marks
the triumph of the forces of reaction towards the close of the
twelfth century—a reaction which destroyed the promising hopes of
freedom of thought and manners which make the twelfth century
appear as a foretaste of modern enlightenment. Here undoubtedly the
change in life corresponds very closely with a great change in
art—the change from the Romanesque to the Gothic, and at first
sight we might suppose a causal connection between the two. But
when we consider the nature of the changes in the two sequences,
this becomes very doubtful. For whereas in the life of the Middle
Ages the change was one of reaction—the sharp repression by the
reactionary forces of a gradual growth of freedom—the change in art
is merely the efflorescence of certain long prepared and
anticipated effects. The forms of Gothic architecture were merely
the answer to certain engineering problems which had long occupied
the inventive ingenuity of twelfth-century architects, while in the
figurative arts the change merely showed a new self-confidence in
the rendering of the human figure, a newly developed mastery in the
handling of material. In short, the change in art was in the
opposite direction to that in life. Whereas in life the direction
of movement was sharply bent backwards, in art the direction
followed on in a continuous straight line.It is true that in one small particular the reaction did have
a direct effect on art. The preaching of S. Bernard of Clairvaux
did impose on the architects who worked for the Cistercian order a
peculiar architectural hypocrisy. They were bound by his
traditional influence to make their churches have an appearance of
extreme simplicity and austerity, but they wanted nevertheless to
make them as magnificent and imposing as possible. The result was a
peculiar style of ostentatious simplicity. Paray le Monial is the
only church left standing in which this curious and, in point of
fact, depressing evidence of the direct influence of the religious
reaction on art is to be seen, and, as a curiosity in psychological
expression, it is well worth a visit. For the rest the movement of
art went on entirely unaffected by the new orientation of
thought.We come now to the Renaissance, and here for the first time
in our survey we may, I think, safely admit a true correspondence
between the change in life and the change in art. The change in
life, if one may generalise on such a vast subject, was towards the
recognition of the rights of the individual to complete
self-realisation and the recognition of the objective reality of
the material universe which implied the whole scientific
attitude—and in both these things the exemplar which men put before
themselves was the civilisation of Greece and Rome. In art the
change wentpari passuwith the
change in life, each assisting and directing the other—the first
men of science were artists like Brunelleschi, Ucello, Piero della
Francesca and Leonardo da Vinci. The study of classical literature
was followed in strict connection with the study of classical
canons of art, and the greater sense of individual importance found
its expression in the new naturalism which made portraiture in the
modern sense possible.For once then art and the other functions of the human spirit
found themselves in perfect harmony and direct alliance, and to
that harmony we may attribute much of the intensity and
self-assurance of the work of the great Renaissance artists. It is
one of the rarest of good fortunes for an artist to find himself
actually understood and appreciated by the mass of his educated
contemporaries, and not only that, but moving alongside of and in
step with them towards a similar goal.The Catholic reaction retarded and impeded the main movement
of Renaissance thought, but it did not really succeed either in
suppressing it or changing the main direction of its current. In
art it undoubtedly had some direct effect, it created a new kind of
insincerity of expression, a florid and sentimental religiosity—a
new variety of bad taste, the rhetorical and over-emphatic. And I
suspect that art was already prepared for this step by a certain
exhaustion of the impulsive energy of the Renaissance—so that here
too we may admit a correspondence.The seventeenth century shows us no violent change in life,
but rather the gradual working out of the principles implicit in
the Renaissance and the Catholic reaction. But here we come to
another curious want of correspondence between art and life, for in
art we have a violent revolution, followed by a bitter internecine
struggle among artists. This revolution was inaugurated by
Caravaggio, who first discovered the surprising emotional
possibilities of chiaroscuro and who combined with this a new idea
of realism—realism in the modern sense, viz., the literal
acceptance of what is coarse, common, squalid or undistinguished in
life—realism in the sense of the novelists of Zola’s time. To
Caravaggio’s influence we might trace not only a great deal of
Rembrandt’s art but the whole of that movement in favour of the
extravagantly impressive and picturesque, which culminated in the
romantic movement of the nineteenth century. Here, then, is another
surprising want of correspondence between art and
life.In the eighteenth century we get a curious phenomenon. Art
goes to court, identifies itself closely with a small aristocratic
clique, becomes the exponent of their manners and their tastes. It
becomes a luxury. It is no longer in the main stream of spiritual
and intellectual effort, and this seclusion of art may account for
the fact that the next great change in life—the French Revolution
and all its accompanying intellectual ferment—finds no serious
correspondence in art. We get a change, it is true; the French
Republicans believed they were the counterpart of the Romans, and
so David had to invent for them that peculiarly distressing type of
the ancient Roman—always in heroic attitudes, always immaculate,
spotless and with a highly polished ‘Mme. Tussaud’ surface.
By-the-by, I was almost forgetting that we do owe Mme. Tussaud to
the French Revolution. But the real movement of art lay in quite
other directions to David—lay in the gradual unfolding of the
Romanticist conception of the world—a world of violent emotional
effects, of picturesque accidents, of wild nature, and this was a
long prepared reaction from the complacent sophistication of
eighteenth-century life. It is possible that one may associate this
with the general state of mind that produced the Revolution, since
both were a revolt against the established order of the eighteenth
century; but curiously enough it found its chief ally in the
reaction which followed the Revolution, in the neo-Christianism of
Chateaubriand and the new sentimental respect for the age of
faith—which, incidentally, appeared so much more picturesque than
the age of reason.It would be interesting at this point to consider how far
during the nineteenth century reactionary political and religious
thought was inspired primarily by æsthetic considerations—a curious
instance of the counter-influence of art on life might perhaps be
discovered in the devotees of the Oxford movement. But this would
take us too far afield.The foregoing violently foreshortened view of history and art
will show, I hope, that the usual assumption of a direct and
decisive connection between life and art is by no means correct. It
may, I hope, give pause to those numerous people who have already
promised themselves a great new art as a result of the present war,
though perhaps it is as well to let them enjoy it in anticipation,
since it is, I fancy, the only way in which they are likely to
enjoy a great art of any kind. What this survey suggests to me is
that if we consider this special spiritual activity of art we find
it no doubt open at times to influences from life, but in the main
self-contained—we find the rhythmic sequences of change determined
much more by its own internal forces—and by the readjustment within
it, of its own elements—than by external forces. I admit, of
course, that it is always conditioned more or less by economic
changes, but these are rather conditions of its existence at all
than directive influences. I also admit that under certain
conditions the rhythms of life and of art may coincide with great
effect on both; but in the main the two rhythms are distinct, and
as often as not play against each other.We have, I hope, gained some experience with which to handle
the real subject of my inquiry, the relation of the modern movement
in art to life. To understand it we must go back to the
impressionist movement, which dates from about 1870. The artists
who called themselves impressionists combined two distinct ideas.
On the one hand they upheld, more categorically than ever before,
the complete detachment of the artistic vision from the values
imposed on vision by everyday life—they claimed, as Whistler did in
his “10 o’clock,” to be pure artists. On the other hand a group of
them used this freedom for the quasi-scientific description of new
effects of atmospheric colour and atmospheric perspective, thereby
endowing painting with a quite new series of colour harmonies, or
at least of harmonies which had not been cultivated by European
painters for many hundreds of years. They did more than this—the
effects thus explored were completely unfamiliar to the ordinary
man, whose vision is limited to the mere recognition of objects
with a view to the uses of everyday life. He was forced, in looking
at their pictures, to accept as artistic representation something
very remote from all his previous expectations, and thereby he also
acquired in time a new tolerance in his judgments on works of art,
a tolerance which was destined to bear a still further strain in
succeeding developments.As against these great advantages which art owes to
impressionism we must set the fact that the pseudo-scientific and
analytic method of these painters forced artists to accept pictures
which lacked design and formal co-ordination to a degree which had
never before been permitted. They, or rather some of them, reduced
the artistic vision to a continuous patchwork or mosaic of coloured
patches without architectural framework or structural coherence. In
this, impressionism marked the climax of a movement which had been
going on more or less steadily from the thirteenth century—the
tendency to approximate the forms of art more and more exactly to
the representation of the totality of appearance. When once
representation had been pushed to this point where further
development was impossible, it was inevitable that artists should
turn round and question the validity of the fundamental assumption
that art aimed at representation; and the moment the question was
fairly posed it became clear that the pseudo-scientific assumption
that fidelity to appearance was the measure of art had no logical
foundation. From that moment on it became evident that art had
arrived at a critical moment, and that the greatest revolution in
art that had taken place since Græco-Roman impressionism became
converted into Byzantine formalism was inevitable. It was this
revolution that Cézanne inaugurated and that Gauguin and van Goch
continued. There is no need here to give in detail the
characteristics of this new movement: they are sufficiently
familiar. But we may summarise them as the re-establishment of
purely æsthetic criteria in place of the criterion of conformity to
appearance—the rediscovery of the principles of structural design
and harmony.The new movement has, also, led to a new canon of criticism,
and this has changed our attitude to the arts of other times and
countries. So long as representation was regarded as the end of
art, the skill of the artist and his proficiency in this particular
feat of representation were regarded with an admiration which was
in fact mainly non-æsthetic. With the new indifference to
representation we have become much less interested in skill and not
at all interested in knowledge. We are thus no longer cut off from
a great deal of barbaric and primitive art the very meaning of
which escaped the understanding of those who demanded a certain
standard of skill in representation before they could give serious
consideration to a work of art. In general the effect of the
movement has been to render the artist intensely conscious of the
æsthetic unity of the work of art, but singularly naïve and simple
as regards other considerations.It remains to be considered whether the life of the past
fifty years has shown any such violent reorientation as we have
found in the history of modern art. If we look back to the days of
Herbert Spencer and Huxley, what changes are there in the general
tendencies of life? The main ideas of rationalism seem to me to
have steadily made way—there have been minor counter revolutions,
it is true, but the main current of active thought has surely moved
steadily along the lines already laid down. I mean that the
scientific attitude is more and more widely accepted. The protests
of organised religion and of various mysticisms seem to grow
gradually weaker and to carry less weight. Hardly any writers or
thinkers of first-rate calibre now appear in the reactionary camp.
I see, in short, no big change in direction, no evident revulsion
of feeling.None the less I suppose that a Spencer would be impossible
now and that the materialism of to-day is recognisably different
from the materialism of Spencer. It would be very much less
naïvely13th Cent. Sculpture in the Cloister of S.
JohnLateranAuguste Rodin. Group from“The Burghers of Calais”Henri Matisse. Sculpture inPlasterProperty of the ArtistPlate I.self-confident. It would admit far greater difficulties in
presenting its picture of the universe than would have occurred to
Spencer. The fact is that scepticism has turned on itself and has
gone behind a great many of the axioms that seemed self-evident to
the earlier rationalists. I do not see that it has at any point
threatened the superstructure of the rationalist position, but it
has led us to recognise the necessity of a continual revision and
reconstruction of these data. Rationalism has become less arrogant
and less narrow in its vision. And this is partly due also to the
adventure of the scientific spirit into new regions. I refer to all
that immense body of study and speculation which starts from
Robertson Smith’s “Religion of the Israelites.” The discovery of
natural law in what seemed to earlier rationalists the chaotic
fancies and caprices of the human imagination. The assumption that
man is a mainly rational animal has given place to the discovery
that he is, like other animals, mainly instinctive. This modifies
immensely the attitude of the rationalist—it gives him a new
charity and a new tolerance. What seemed like the wilful follies of
mad or wicked men to the earlier rationalists are now seen to be
inevitable responses to fundamental instinctive needs. By observing
mankind the man of science has lost his contempt for him. Now this
I think has had an important bearing on the new movement in art. In
the first place I find something analogous in the new orientation
of scientific and artistic endeavour. Science has turned its
instruments in on human nature and begun to investigate its
fundamental needs, and art has also turned its vision inwards, has
begun to work upon the fundamental necessities of man’s æsthetic
functions.But besides this analogy, which may be merely accidental and
not causal, I think there can be little doubt that the new
scientific development (for it is in no sense a revolution) has
modified men’s attitude to art. To Herbert Spencer religion was
primitive fear of the unknown and art was sexual attraction—he must
have contemplated with perfect equanimity, almost with
satisfaction, a world in which both these functions would
disappear. I suppose that the scientific man of to-day would be
much more ready to admit not only the necessity but the great
importance of æsthetic feeling for the spiritual existence of man.
The general conception of life in the mid-nineteenth century ruled
out art as noxious, or at best, a useless frivolity, and above all
as a mere survival of more primitive stages of
evolution.On the other hand, the artist of the new movement is moving
into a sphere more and more remote from that of the ordinary man.
In proportion as art becomes purer the number of people to whom it
appeals gets less. It cuts out all the romantic overtones of life
which are the usual bait by which men are induced to accept a work
of art. It appeals only to the æsthetic sensibility, and that in
most men is comparatively weak.In the modern movement in art, then, as in so many cases in
past history, the revolution in art seems to be out of all
proportion to any corresponding change in life as a whole. It seems
to find its sources, if at all, in what at present seem like minor
movements. Whether the difference between the nineteenth and
twentieth centuries will in retrospect seem as great in life as
they already do in art I cannot guess—at least it is curious to
note how much more conscious we are of the change in art then we
are in the general change in thought and feeling.Note.—The original lecture was not illustrated, but the
opportunity of publishing this summary of it has suggested the
possibility of introducing a few examples to illustrate one point,
viz., the extent to which the works of the new movement correspond
in aim with the works of early art while being sharply contrasted
with those of the penultimate period. This will be, perhaps, most
evident inPlate
I, where I have placed a figure from the
cloisters of S. John Lateran, carved by a thirteenth-century
sculptor—then one of Rodin’sBurghers of
Calais, and then Matisse’s unfinished
alto-rilievo figure. Here there is no need to underline the
startling difference shown by Rodin’s descriptive method from the
more purely plastic feeling of the two other artists. Matisse and
the thirteenth-century artist are much closer together than Matisse
and Rodin.InPlate III have placed Picasso
beside Raphael. Here the obvious fact is the common preoccupation
of both artists with certain problems of plastic design and the
similarity of their solutions. Had I had space to put a Sargent
beside these the same violent contrast would have been
produced.Raphael. “La Donna Gravida”Pitti Palace, FlorencePablo Picasso. Portrait of Miss Gertrude
SteinMiss Gertrude SteinPlate II.
A CERTAIN painter, not without some reputation at the present
day, once wrote a little book on the art he practises, in which he
gave a definition of that art so succinct that I take it as a point
of departure for this essay.
“ The art of painting,” says that eminent authority, “is the
art of imitating solid objects upon a flat surface by means of
pigments.” It is delightfully simple, but prompts the question—Is
that all? And, if so, what a deal of unnecessary fuss has been made
about it. Now, it is useless to deny that our modern writer has
some very respectable authorities behind him. Plato, indeed, gave a
very similar account of the affair, and himself put the question—is
it then worth while? And, being scrupulously and relentlessly
logical, he decided that it was not worth while, and proceeded to
turn the artists out of his ideal republic. For all that, the world
has continued obstinately to consider that painting was worth
while, and though, indeed, it has never quite made up its mind as
to what, exactly, the graphic arts did for it, it has persisted in
honouring and admiring its painters.
Can we arrive at any conclusions as to the nature of the
graphic arts, which will at all explain our feelings about them,
which will at least put them into some kind of relation with the
other arts, and not leave us in the extreme perplexity, engendered
by any theory of mere imitation? For, I suppose, it must be
admitted that if imitation is the sole purpose of the graphic arts,
it is surprising that the works of such arts are ever looked upon
as more than curiosities, or ingenious toys, are ever taken
seriously by grown-up people. Moreover, it will be surprising that
they have no recognisable affinity with other arts, such as music
or architecture, in which the imitation of actual objects is a
negligible quantity.
To form such conclusions is the aim I have put before myself
in this essay. Even if the results are not decisive, the inquiry
may lead us to a view of the graphic arts that will not be
altogether unfruitful.
I must begin with some elementary psychology, with a
consideration of the nature of instincts. A great many objects in
the world, when presented to our senses, put in motion a complex
nervous machinery, which ends in some instinctive appropriate
action. We see a wild bull in a field; quite without our conscious
interference a nervous process goes on, which, unless we interfere
forcibly, ends in the appropriate reaction of flight. The nervous
mechanism which results in flight causes a certain state of
consciousness, which we call the emotion of fear. The whole of
animal life, and a great part of human life, is made up of these
instinctive reactions to sensible objects, and their accompanying
emotions. But man has the peculiar faculty of calling up again in
his mind the echo of past experiences of this kind, of going over
it again, “in imagination” as we say. He has, therefore, the
possibility of a double life; one the actual life, the other the
imaginative life. Between these two lives there is this great
distinction, that in the actual life the processes of natural
selection have brought it about that the instinctive reaction,
such, for instance, as flight from danger, shall be the important
part of the whole process, and it is towards this that the man
bends his whole conscious endeavour. But in the imaginative life no
such action is necessary, and, therefore, the whole consciousness
may be focussed upon the perceptive and the emotional aspects of
the experience. In this way we get, in the imaginative life, a
different set of values, and a different kind of perception.
We can get a curious side glimpse of the nature of this
imaginative life from the cinematograph. This resembles actual life
in almost every respect, except that what the psychologists call
the conative part of our reaction to sensations, that is to say,
the appropriate resultant action is cut off. If, in a
cinematograph, we see a runaway horse and cart, we do not have to
think either of getting out of the way or heroically interposing
ourselves. The result is that in the first place weseethe event much more clearly; see a number of
quite interesting but irrelevant things, which in real life could
not struggle into our consciousness, bent, as it would be, entirely
upon the problem of our appropriate reaction. I remember seeing in
a cinematograph the arrival of a train at a foreign station and the
people descending from the carriages; there was no platform, and to
my intense surprise I saw several people turn right round after
reaching the ground, as though to orientate themselves; an almost
ridiculous performance, which I had never noticed in all the many
hundred occasions on which such a scene had passed before my eyes
in real life. The fact being that at a station one is never really
a spectator of events, but an actor engaged in the drama of luggage
or prospective seats, and one actually sees only so much as may
help to the appropriate action.
In the second place, with regard to the visions of the
cinematograph, one notices that whatever emotions are aroused by
them, though they are likely to be weaker than those of ordinary
life, are presented more clearly to the consciousness. If the scene
presented be one of an accident, our pity and horror, though weak,
since we know that no one is really hurt, are felt quite purely,
since they cannot, as they would in life, pass at once into actions
of assistance.
A somewhat similar effect to that of the cinematograph can be
obtained by watching a mirror in which a street scene is reflected.
If we look at the street itself we are almost sure to adjust
ourselves in some way to its actual existence. We recognise an
acquaintance, and wonder why he looks so dejected this morning, or
become interested in a new fashion in hats—the moment we do that
the spell is broken, we are reacting to life itself in however
slight a degree, but, in the mirror, it is easier to abstract
ourselves completely, and look upon the changing scene as a whole.
It then, at once, takes on the visionary quality, and we become
true spectators, not selecting what we will see, but seeing
everything equally, and thereby we come to notice a number of
appearances and relations of appearances, which would have escaped
our vision before, owing to that perpetual economising by selection
of what impressions we will assimilate, which in life we perform by
unconscious processes. The frame of the mirror then, does, to some
extent, turn the reflected scene from one that belongs to our
actual life into one that belongs rather to the imaginative life.
The frame of the mirror makes its surface into a very rudimentary
work of art, since it helps us to attain to the artistic vision.
For that is what, as you will already have guessed, I have been
coming to all this time, namely that the work of art is intimately
connected with the secondary imaginative life, which all men live
to a greater or lesser extent.
That the graphic arts are the expression of the imaginative
life rather than a copy of actual life might be guessed from
observing children. Children, if left to themselves, never, I
believe, copy what they see, never, as we say, “draw from nature,”
but express, with a delightful freedom and sincerity, the mental
images which make up their own imaginative lives.
Art, then, is an expression and a stimulus of this
imaginative life, which is separated from actual life by the
absence of responsive action. Now this responsive action implies in
actual life moral responsibility. In art we have no such moral
responsibility—it presents a life freed from the binding
necessities of our actual existence.
What then is the justification for this life of the
imagination which all human beings live more or less fully? To the
pure moralist, who accepts nothing but ethical values, in order to
be justified, it must be shown not onlynotto hinder but actually to forward right action, otherwise it
is not only useless but, since it absorbs our energies, positively
harmful. To such a one two views are possible, one the Puritanical
view at its narrowest, which regards the life of the imagination as
no better or worse than a life of sensual pleasure, and therefore
entirely reprehensible. The other view is to argue that the
imaginative life does subserve morality. And this is inevitably the
view taken by moralists like Ruskin, to whom the imaginative life
is yet an absolute necessity. It is a view which leads to some very
hard special pleading, even to a self-deception which is in itself
morally undesirable.
But here comes in the question of religion, for religion is
also an affair of the imaginative life, and, though it claims to
have a direct effect upon conduct, I do not suppose that the
religious person if he were wise would justify religion entirely by
its effect on morality, since that, historically speaking, has not
been by any means uniformly advantageous. He would probably say
that the religious experience was one which corresponded to certain
spiritual capacities of human nature, the exercise of which is in
itself good and desirable apart from their effect upon actual life.
And so, too, I think the artist might if he chose take a mystical
attitude, and declare that the fullness and completeness of the
imaginative life he leads may correspond to an existence more real
and more important than any that we know of in mortal life.
And in saying that, his appeal would find a sympathetic echo
in most minds, for most people would, I think, say that the
pleasures derived from art were of an altogether different
character and more fundamental than merely sensual pleasures, that
they did exercise some faculties which are felt to belong to
whatever part of us there may be which is not entirely ephemeral
and material.
It might even be that from this point of view we should
rather justify actual life by its relation to the imaginative,
justify nature by its likeness to art. I mean this, that since the
imaginative life comes in the course of time to represent more or
less what mankind feels to be the completest expression of its own
nature, the freest use of its innate capacities, the actual life
may be explained and justified in its approximation here and there,
however partially and inadequately, to that freer and fuller
life.
Before leaving this question of the justification of art, let
me put it in another way. The imaginative life of a people has very
different levels at different times, and these levels do not always
correspond with the general level of the morality of actual life.
Thus in the thirteenth century we read of barbarity and cruelty
which would shock even us; we may I think admit that our moral
level, our general humanity is decidedly higher to-day, but the
level of our imaginative life is incomparably lower; we are
satisfied there with a grossness, a sheer barbarity and squalor
which would have shocked the thirteenth century profoundly. Let us
admit the moral gain gladly, but do we not also feel a loss; do we
not feel that the average business man would be in every way a more
admirable, more respectable being if his imaginative life were not
so squalid and incoherent? And, if we admit any loss then, there is
some function in human nature other than a purely ethical one,
which is worthy of exercise.
Now the imaginative life has its own history both in the race
and in the individual. In the individual life one of the first
effects of freeing experience from the necessities of appropriate
responsive action is to indulge recklessly the emotion of
self-aggrandisement. The day-dreams of a child are filled with
extravagant romances in which he is always the invincible hero.
Music—which of all the arts supplies the strongest stimulus to the
imaginative life, and at the same time has the least power of
controlling its direction—music, at certain stages of people’s
lives, has the effect merely of arousing in an almost absurd degree
this egoistic elation, and Tolstoy appears to believe that this is
its only possible effect. But with the teaching of experience and
the growth of character the imaginative life comes to respond to
other instincts and to satisfy other desires, until, indeed, it
reflects the highest aspirations and the deepest aversions of which
human nature is capable.
In dreams and when under the influence of drugs the
imaginative life passes out of our own control, and in such cases
its experiences may be highly undesirable, but whenever it remains
under our own control it must always be on the whole a desirable
life. That is not to say that it is always pleasant, for it is
pretty clear that mankind is so constituted as to desire much
besides pleasure, and we shall meet among the great artists, the
great exponents, that is, of the imaginative life, many to whom the
merely pleasant is very rarely a part of what is desirable. But
this desirability of the imaginative life does distinguish it very
sharply from actual life, and is the direct result of that first
fundamental difference, its freedom from necessary external
conditions. Art, then, is, if I am right, the chief organ of the
imaginative life, it is by art that it is stimulated and controlled
within us, and, as we have seen, the imaginative life is
distinguished by the greater clearness of its perception, and the
greater purity and freedom of its emotion.
First with regard to the greater clearness of perception. The
needs of our actual life are so imperative, that the sense of
vision becomes highly specialised in their service. With an
admirable economy we learn to see only so much as is needful for
our purposes; but this is in fact very little, just enough to
recognise and identify each object or person; that done, they go
into an entry in our mental catalogue and are no more really seen.
In actual life the normal person really only reads the labels as it
were on the objects around him and troubles no further. Almost all
the things which are useful in any way put on more or less this cap
of invisibility. It is only when an object exists in our lives for
no other purpose than to be seen that we really look at it, as for
instance at a China ornament or a precious stone, and towards such
even the most normal person adopts to some extent the artistic
attitude of pure vision abstracted from necessity.
Now this specialisation of vision goes so far that ordinary
people have almost no idea of what things really look like, so that
oddly enough the one standard that popular criticism applies to
painting, namely, whether it is like nature or not, is one which
most people are, by the whole tenour of their lives, prevented from
applying properly. The only things they have ever reallylookedat being other pictures; the moment an
artist who has looked at nature brings to them a clear report of
something definitely seen by him, they are wildly indignant at its
untruth to nature. This has happened so constantly in our own time
that there is no need to prove it. One instance will suffice. Monet
is an artist whose chief claim to recognition lies in the fact of
his astonishing power of faithfully reproducing certain aspects of
nature, but his really naïve innocence and sincerity was taken by
the public to be the most audacious humbug, and it required the
teaching of men like Bastien-Lepage, who cleverly compromised
between the truth and an accepted convention of what things looked
like, to bring the world gradually round to admitting truths which
a single walk in the country with purely unbiassed vision would
have established beyond doubt.
But though this clarified sense perception which we discover
in the imaginative life is of great interest, and although it plays
a larger part in the graphic arts than in any other, it might
perhaps be doubted whether, interesting, curious, fascinating as it
is, this aspect of the imaginative life would ever by itself make
art of profound importance to mankind. But it is different, I
think, with the emotional aspect. We have admitted that the
emotions of the imaginative are generally weaker than those of
actual life. The picture of a saint being slowly flayed alive,
revolting as it is, will not produce the actual physical sensations
of sickening disgust that a modern man would feel if he could
assist at the actual event; but they have a compensating clearness
of presentment to the consciousness. The more poignant emotions of
actual life have, I think, a kind of numbing effect analogous to
the paralysing influence of fear in some animals; but even if this
experience be not generally admitted, all will admit that the need
for responsive action hurries us along and prevents us from ever
realising fully what the emotion is that we feel, from
co-ordinating it perfectly with other states. In short, the motives
we actually experience are too close to us to enable us to feel
them clearly. They are in a sense unintelligible. In the
imaginative life, on the contrary, we can both feel the emotion and
watch it. When we are really moved at the theatre we are always
both on the stage and in the auditorium.
Yet another point about the emotions of the imaginative
life—since they require no responsive action we can give them a new
valuation. In real life we must to some extent cultivate those
emotions which lead to useful action, and we are bound to appraise
emotions according to the resultant action. So that, for instance,
the feelings of rivalry and emulation do get an encouragement which
perhaps they scarcely deserve, whereas certain feelings which
appear to have a high intrinsic value get almost no stimulus in
actual life. For instance, those feelings to which the name of the
cosmic emotion has been somewhat unhappily given find almost no
place in life, but, since they seem to belong to certain very deep
springs of our nature, do become of great importance in the
arts.
Morality, then, appreciates emotion by the standard of
resultant action. Art appreciates emotion in and for itself.
This view of the essential importance in art of the
expression of the emotions is the basis of Tolstoy’s marvellously
original and yet perverse and even exasperating book, “What is
Art,” and I willingly confess, while disagreeing with almost all
his results, how much I owe to him.
He gives an example of what he means by calling art the means
of communicating emotions. He says, let us suppose a boy to have
been pursued in the forest by a bear. If he returns to the village
and merely states that he was pursued by a bear and escaped, that
is ordinary language, the means of communicating facts or ideas;
but if he describes his state first of heedlessness, then of sudden
alarm and terror as the bear appears, and finally of relief when he
gets away, and describes this so that his hearers share his
emotions, then his description is a work of art.
Now in so far as the boy does this in order to urge the
villagers to go out and kill the bear, though he may be using
artistic methods, his speech is not a pure work of art; but if of a
winter evening the boy relates his experience for the sake of the
enjoyment of his adventure in retrospect, or better still, if he
makes up the whole story for the sake of the imagined emotions,
then his speech becomes a pure work of art. But Tolstoy takes the
other view, and values the emotions aroused by art entirely for
their reaction upon actual life, a view which he courageously
maintains even when it leads him to condemn the whole of
Michelangelo, Raphael and Titian, and most of Beethoven, not to
mention nearly everything he himself has written, as bad or false
art.