INTRODUCTION
For
the study of the great writers and thinkers of the past, historical
imagination is the first necessity. Without mentally referring to
the
environment in which they lived, we cannot hope to penetrate below
the inessential and temporary to the absolute and permanent value
of
their thought. Theory, no less than action, is subject to these
necessities; the form in which men cast their speculations, no less
than the ways in which they behave, are the result of the habits of
thought and action which they find around them. Great men make,
indeed, individual contributions to the knowledge of their times;
but
they can never transcend the age in which they live. The questions
they try to answer will always be those their contemporaries are
asking; their statement of fundamental problems will always be
relative to the traditional statements that have been handed down
to
them. When they are stating what is most startlingly new, they will
be most likely to put it in an old-fashioned form, and to use the
inadequate ideas and formulae of tradition to express the deeper
truths towards which they are feeling their way. They will be most
the children of their age, when they are rising most above
it.Rousseau
has suffered as much as any one from critics without a sense of
history. He has been cried up and cried down by democrats and
oppressors with an equal lack of understanding and imagination. His
name, a hundred and fifty years after the publication of the
Social Contract, is
still a controversial watchword and a party cry. He is accepted as
one of the greatest writers France has produced; but even now men
are
inclined, as political bias prompts them, to accept or reject his
political doctrines as a whole, without sifting them or attempting
to
understand and discriminate. He is still revered or hated as the
author who, above all others, inspired the French
Revolution.At
the present day, his works possess a double significance. They are
important historically, alike as giving us an insight into the mind
of the eighteenth century, and for the actual influence they have
had
on the course of events in Europe. Certainly no other writer of the
time has exercised such an influence as his. He may fairly be
called
the parent of the romantic movement in art, letters and life; he
affected profoundly the German romantics and Goethe himself; he set
the fashion of a new introspection which has permeated nineteenth
century literature; he began modern educational theory; and, above
all, in political thought he represents the passage from a
traditional theory rooted in the Middle Ages to the modern
philosophy
of the State. His influence on Kant's moral philosophy and on
Hegel's
philosophy of Right are two sides of the same fundamental
contribution to modern thought. He is, in fact, the great
forerunner
of German and English Idealism.It
would not be possible, in the course of a short introduction, to
deal
both with the positive content of Rousseau's thought and with the
actual influence he has had on practical affairs. The statesmen of
the French Revolution, from Robespierre downwards, were throughout
profoundly affected by the study of his works. Though they seem
often
to have misunderstood him, they had on the whole studied him with
the
attention he demands. In the nineteenth century, men continued to
appeal to Rousseau, without, as a rule, knowing him well or
penetrating deeply into his meaning. "The
Social Contract,"
says M. Dreyfus-Brisac, "is the book of all books that is most
talked of and least read." But with the great revival of
interest in political philosophy there has come a desire for the
better understanding of Rousseau's work. He is again being studied
more as a thinker and less as an ally or an opponent; there is more
eagerness to sift the true from the false, and to seek in
the
Social Contract the
"principles of political right," rather than the great
revolutionary's ipse
dixit in favour of
some view about circumstances which he could never have;
contemplated.The
Social Contract,
then, may be regarded either as a document of the French
Revolution,
or as one of the greatest books dealing with political philosophy.
It
is in the second capacity, as a work of permanent value containing
truth, that it finds a place among the world's great books. It is
in
that capacity also that it will be treated in this introduction.
Taking it in this aspect, we have no less need of historical
insight
than if we came to it as historians pure and simple. To
understand—its value we must grasp its limitations; when the
questions it answers seem unnaturally put, we must not conclude
that
they are meaningless; we must see if the answer still holds when
the
question is put in a more up-to-date form.First,
then, we must always remember that Rousseau is writing in the
eighteenth century, and for the most part in France. Neither the
French monarchy nor the Genevese aristocracy loved outspoken
criticism, and Rousseau had always to be very careful what he said.
This may seem a curious statement to make about a man who suffered
continual persecution on account of his subversive doctrines; but,
although Rousseau was one of the most daring writers of his time,
he
was forced continually to moderate his language and, as a rule, to
confine himself to generalisation instead of attacking particular
abuses. Rousseau's theory has often been decried as too abstract
and
metaphysical. This is in many ways its great strength; but where it
is excessively so, the accident of time is to blame. In the
eighteenth century it was, broadly speaking, safe to generalise and
unsafe to particularise. Scepticism and discontent were the
prevailing temper of the intellectual classes, and a short-sighted
despotism held that, as long as they were confined to these, they
would do little harm. Subversive doctrines were only regarded as
dangerous when they were so put as to appeal to the masses;
philosophy was regarded as impotent. The intellectuals of the
eighteenth century therefore generalised to their hearts' content,
and as a rule suffered little for their
lèse-majesté:
Voltaire is the typical example of such generalisation. The spirit
of
the age favoured such methods, and it was therefore natural for
Rousseau to pursue them. But his general remarks had such a way of
bearing very obvious particular applications, and were so obviously
inspired by a particular attitude towards the government of his
day,
that even philosophy became in his hands unsafe, and he was
attacked
for what men read between the lines of his works. It is owing to
this
faculty of giving his generalisations content and actuality that
Rousseau has become the father of modern political philosophy. He
uses the method of his time only to transcend it; out of the
abstract
and general he creates the concrete and universal.Secondly,
we must not forget that Rousseau's theories are to be studied in a
wider historical environment. If he is the first of modern
political
theorists, he is also the last of a long line of Renaissance
theorists, who in turn inherit and transform the concepts of
mediæval
thought. So many critics have spent so much wasted time in proving
that Rousseau was not original only because they began by
identifying
originality with isolation: they studied first the
Social Contract by
itself, out of relation to earlier works, and then, having
discovered
that these earlier works resembled it, decided that everything it
had
to say was borrowed. Had they begun their study in a truly
historical
spirit, they would have seen that Rousseau's importance lies just
in
the new use he makes of old ideas, in the transition he makes from
old to new in the general conception of politics. No mere innovator
could have exercised such an influence or hit on so much truth.
Theory makes no great leaps; it proceeds to new concepts by the
adjustment and renovation of old ones. Just as theological writers
on
politics, from Hooker to Bossuet, make use of Biblical terminology
and ideas; just as more modern writers, from Hegel to Herbert
Spencer, make use of the concept of evolution, Rousseau uses the
ideas and terms of the Social Contract theory. We should feel,
throughout his work, his struggle to free himself from what is
lifeless and outworn in that theory, while he develops out of it
fruitful conceptions that go beyond its scope. A too rigid
literalism
in the interpretation of Rousseau's thought may easily reduce it to
the possession of a merely "historical interest": if we
approach it in a truly historical spirit, we shall be able to
appreciate at once its temporary and its lasting value, to see how
it
served his contemporaries, and at the same time to disentangle from
it what may be serviceable to us and for all time.Rousseau's
Emile, the greatest
of all works on education, has already been issued in this series.
In
this volume are contained the most important of his political
works.
Of these the Social
Contract, by far
the most significant, is the latest in date. It represents the
maturity of his thought, while the other works only illustrate his
development. Born in 1712, he issued no work of importance till
1750;
but he tells us, in the
Confessions, that
in 1743, when he was attached to the Embassy at Venice, he had
already conceived the idea of a great work on
Political Institutions,
"which was to put the seal on his reputation." He seems,
however, to have made little progress with this work, until in 1749
he happened to light on the announcement of a prize offered by the
Academy of Dijon for an answer to the question, "Has the
progress of the arts and sciences tended to the purification or to
the corruption of morality?" His old ideas came thronging back,
and sick at heart of the life he had been leading among the
Paris
lumières, he
composed a violent and rhetorical diatribe against civilisation
generally. In the following year, this work, having been awarded
the
prize by the Academy, was published by its author. His success was
instantaneous; he became at once a famous man, the "lion"
of Parisian literary circles. Refutations of his work were issued
by
professors, scribblers, outraged theologians and even by the King
of
Poland. Rousseau endeavoured to answer them all, and in the course
of
argument his thought developed. From 1750 to the publication of
the
Social Contract and
Emile in 1762 he
gradually evolved his views: in those twelve years he made his
unique
contribution to political thought.The
Discourse on the Arts and Sciences,
the earliest of the works reproduced in this volume, is not in
itself
of very great importance. Rousseau has given his opinion of it in
the
Confessions. "Full
of warmth and force, it is wholly without logic or order; of all my
works it is the weakest in argument and the least harmonious. But
whatever gifts a man may be born with, he cannot learn the art of
writing in a moment." This criticism is just. The first
Discourse neither is, nor attempts to be, a reasoned or a balanced
production. It is the speech of an advocate, wholly one-sided and
arbitrary, but so obviously and naively one-sided, that it is
difficult for us to believe in its entire seriousness. At the most,
it is only a rather brilliant but flimsy rhetorical effort, a
sophistical improvisation, but not a serious contribution to
thought.
Yet it is certain that this declamation made Rousseau's name, and
established his position as a great writer in Parisian circles.
D'Alembert even devoted the preface of the
Encyclopædia to a
refutation. The plan of the first Discourse is essentially simple:
it
sets out from the badness, immorality and misery of modern nations,
traces all these ills to the departure from a "natural"
state, and then credits the progress of the arts and sciences with
being the cause of that departure. In it, Rousseau is already in
possession of his idea of "nature" as an ideal; but he has
at present made no attempt to discriminate, in what is unnatural,
between good and bad. He is merely using a single idea, putting it
as
strongly as he can, and neglecting all its limitations. The first
Discourse is important not for any positive doctrine it contains,
but
as a key to the development of Rousseau's mind. Here we see him at
the beginning of the long journey which was to lead on at last to
the
theory of the Social
Contract.In
1755 appeared the
Discourse on the Origin and Foundation of Inequality among Men,
which is the second of the works given in this volume. With this
essay, Rousseau had unsuccessfully competed in 1753 for a second
prize offered by the Academy of Dijon, and he now issued it
prefaced
by a long Dedication to the Republic of Geneva. In this work, which
Voltaire, in thanking him for a presentation copy, termed his
"second
book against the human race," his style and his ideas have made
a great advance; he is no longer content merely to push a single
idea
to extremes: while preserving the broad opposition between the
state
of nature and the state of society, which runs through all his
work,
he is concerned to present a rational justification of his views
and
to admit that a little at any rate may be said on the other side.
Moreover, the idea of "nature" has already undergone a
great development; it is no longer an empty opposition to the evils
of society; it possesses a positive content. Thus half the
Discourse on Inequality
is occupied by an imaginary description of the state of nature, in
which man is shown with ideas limited within the narrowest range,
with little need of his fellows, and little care beyond provision
for
the necessities of the moment. Rousseau declares explicitly that he
does not suppose the "state of nature" ever to have
existed: it is a pure "idea of reason," a working concept
reached by abstraction from the "state of society." The
"natural man," as opposed to "man's man," is man
stripped of all that society confers upon him, a creature formed by
a
process of abstraction, and never intended for a historical
portrait.
The conclusion of the Discourse favours not this purely abstract
being, but a state of savagery intermediate between the "natural"
and the "social" conditions, in which men may preserve the
simplicity and the advantages of nature and at the same time secure
the rude comforts and assurances of early society. In one of the
long
notes appended to the Discourse, Rousseau further explains his
position. He does not wish, he says, that modern corrupt society
should return to a state of nature: corruption has gone too far for
that; he only desires now that men should palliate, by wiser use of
the fatal arts, the mistake of their introduction. He recognises
society as inevitable and is already feeling his way towards a
justification of it. The second Discourse represents a second stage
in his political thought: the opposition between the state of
nature
and the state of society is still presented in naked contrast; but
the picture of the former has already filled out, and it only
remains
for Rousseau to take a nearer view of the fundamental implications
of
the state of society for his thought to reach maturity.Rousseau
is often blamed, by modern critics, for pursuing in the Discourses
a
method apparently that of history, but in reality wholly
unhistorical. But it must be remembered that he himself lays no
stress on the historical aspect of his work; he gives himself out
as
constructing a purely ideal picture, and not as depicting any
actual
stages in human history. The use of false historical concepts is
characteristic of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, and
Rousseau is more to be congratulated on having escaped from giving
them too much importance than criticised for employing them at
all.It
is doubtful whether the
Discourse on Political Economy,
first printed in the great
Encyclopædia in
1755, was composed before or after the
Discourse on Inequality.
At first sight the former seems to be far more in the manner of
the
Social Contract and
to contain views belonging essentially to Rousseau's constructive
period. It would not, however, be safe to conclude from this that
its
date is really later. The
Discourse on Inequality
still has about it much of the rhetorical looseness of the prize
essay; it aims not so much at close reasoning as at effective and
popular presentation of a case. But, by reading between the lines,
an
attentive student can detect in it a great deal of the positive
doctrine afterwards incorporated in the
Social Contract.
Especially in the closing section, which lays down the plan of a
general treatment of the fundamental questions of politics, we are
already to some extent in the atmosphere of the later works. It is
indeed almost certain that Rousseau never attempted to put into
either of the first two Discourses any of the positive content of
his
political theory. They were intended, not as final expositions of
his
point of view, but as partial and preliminary studies, in which his
aim was far more destructive than constructive. It is clear that in
first conceiving the plan of a work on
Political Institutions,
Rousseau cannot have meant to regard all society as in essence bad.
It is indeed evident that he meant, from the first, to study human
society and institutions in their rational aspect, and that he was
rather diverted from his main purpose by the Academy of Dijon's
competition than first induced by it to think about political
questions. It need, therefore, cause no surprise that a work
probably
written before the
Discourse on Inequality
should contain the germs of the theory given in full in the
Social Contract.
The Discourse on
Political Economy
is important as giving the first sketch of the theory of the
"General
Will." It will readily be seen that Rousseau does not mean by
"political economy" exactly what we mean nowadays. He
begins with a discussion of the fundamental nature of the State,
and
the possibility of reconciling its existence with human liberty,
and
goes on with an admirable short study of the principles of
taxation.
He is thinking throughout of "political" in the sense of
"public" economy, of the State as the public financier, and
not of the conditions governing industry. He conceives the State as
a
body aiming at the well-being of all its members and subordinates
all
his views of taxation to that end. He who has only necessaries
should
not be taxed at all; superfluities should be supertaxed; there
should
be heavy imposts on every sort of luxury. The first part of the
article is still more interesting. Rousseau begins by demolishing
the
exaggerated parallel so often drawn between the State and the
family;
he shows that the State is not, and cannot be, patriarchal in
nature,
and goes on to lay down his view that its real being consists in
the
General Will of its members. The essential features of the
Social Contract are
present in this Discourse almost as if they were commonplaces,
certainly not as if they were new discoveries on which the author
had
just hit by some happy inspiration. There is every temptation,
after
reading the
Political Economy,
to suppose that Rousseau's political ideas really reached maturity
far earlier than has generally been allowed.The
Social Contract
finally appeared, along with
Emile, in 1762.
This year, therefore, represents in every respect the culmination
of
Rousseau's career. Henceforth, he was to write only controversial
and
confessional works; his theories were now developed, and,
simultaneously, he gave to the world his views on the fundamental
problems of politics and education. It is now time to ask what
Rousseau's system, in its maturity, finally amounted to The
Social Contract
contains practically the whole of his constructive political
theory;
it requires to be read, for full understanding, in connection with
his other works, especially
Emile and the
Letters on the Mount
(1764), but in the main it is self-contained and complete. The
title
sufficiently defines its scope. It is called
The Social Contract or Principles of Political Right,
and the second title explains the first. Rousseau's object is not
to
deal, in a general way, like Montesquieu, with the actual
institutions of existing States, but to lay down the essential
principles which must form the basis of every legitimate society.
Rousseau himself, in the fifth book of the
Emile, has stated
the difference clearly. "Montesquieu," he says, "did
not intend to treat of the principles of political right; he was
content to treat of the positive right (or law) of established
governments; and no two studies could be more different than
these."
Rousseau then conceives his object as being something very
different
from that of the
Spirit of the Laws,
and it is a wilful error to misconstrue his purpose. When he
remarks
that "the facts," the actual history of political
societies, "do not concern him," he is not contemptuous of
facts; he is merely asserting the sure principle that a fact can in
no case give rise to a right. His desire is to establish society on
a
basis of pure right, so as at once to disprove his attack on
society
generally and to reinforce his criticism of existing
societies.Round
this point centres the whole dispute about the methods proper to
political theory. There are, broadly speaking, two schools of
political theorists, if we set aside the psychologists. One school,
by collecting facts, aims at reaching broad generalisations about
what actually happens in human societies! the other tries to
penetrate to the universal principles at the root of all human
combination. For the latter purpose facts may be useful, but in
themselves they can prove nothing. The question is not one of fact,
but one of right.Rousseau
belongs essentially to this philosophical school. He is not, as his
less philosophic critics seem to suppose, a purely abstract thinker
generalising from imaginary historical instances; he is a concrete
thinker trying to get beyond they inessential and changing to the
permanent and invariable basis of human society. Like Green, he is
in
search of the principle of political obligation, and beside this
quest all others fall into their place as secondary and derivative.
It is required to find a form of association able to defend and
protect with the whole common force the person and goods of every
associate, and of such a nature, that each, uniting himself with
all,
may still obey only himself, and remain as free as before. This is
the fundamental problem of which the
Social Contract
provides the solution. The problem of political obligation is seen
as
including all other political problems, which fall into place in a
system based upon it. How, Rousseau asks, can the will of the State
help being for me a merely external will, imposing itself upon my
own? How can the existence of the State be reconciled with human
freedom? How can man, who is born free, rightly come to be
everywhere
in chains?No-one
could help understanding the central problem of the
Social Contract
immediately, were it not that its doctrines often seem to be
strangely formulated. We have seen that this strangeness is due to
Rousseau's historical position, to his use of the political
concepts
current in his own age, and to his natural tendency to build on the
foundations laid by his predecessors. There are a great many people
whose idea of Rousseau consists solely of the first words of the
opening chapter of the
Social Contract,
"Man is born free, and everywhere he is in chains." But,
they tell you, man is not born free, even if he is everywhere in
chains. Thus at the very outset we are faced with the great
difficulty in appreciating Rousseau. When we should naturally say
"man ought to be free," or perhaps "man is born for
freedom," he prefers to say "man is born free," by
which he means exactly the same thing. There is doubtless, in his
way
of putting it, an appeal to a "golden age"; but this golden
age is admittedly as imaginary as the freedom to which men are born
is bound, for most of them, to be. Elsewhere Rousseau puts the
point
much as we might put it ourselves. "Nothing is more certain than
that every man born in slavery is born for slavery.... But if there
are slaves by nature, it is because there have been slaves against
nature" (Social
Contract, Book I,
chap. ii).We
have seen that the contrast between the "state of nature"
and the "state of society" runs through all Rousseau's
work. The Emile
is a plea for "natural" education; the Discourses are a
plea for a "naturalisation" of society; the
New Héloïse is
the romantic's appeal for more "nature" in human
relationships. What then is the position of this contrast in
Rousseau's mature political thought? It is clear that the position
is
not merely that of the Discourses. In them, he envisaged only the
faults of actual societies; now, he is concerned with the
possibility
of a rational society. His aim is to justify the change from
"nature"
to "society," although it has left men in chains. He is in
search of the true society, which leaves men "as free as
before." Altogether, the space occupied by the idea of nature in
the Social Contract
is very small. It is used of necessity in the controversial
chapters,
in which Rousseau is refuting false theories of social obligation;
but when once he has brushed aside the false prophets, he lets the
idea of nature go with them, and concerns himself solely with
giving
society the rational sanction he has promised. It becomes clear
that,
in political matters at any rate, the "state of nature" is
for him only a term of controversy. He has in effect abandoned, in
so
far as he ever held it, the theory of a human golden age; and
where,
as in the Emile,
he makes use of the idea of nature, it is broadened and deepened
out
of all recognition. Despite many passages in which the old
terminology cleaves to him, he means by "nature" in this
period not the original state of a thing, nor even its reduction to
the simplest terms: he is passing over to the conception of
"nature"
as identical with the full development of capacity, with the
higher!
idea of human freedom. This view may be seen in germ even in
the
Discourse on Inequality,
where, distinguishing self-respect (amour
de soi) from egoism
(amour-propre),
Rousseau makes the former, the property of the "natural"
man, consist not in the desire for self-aggrandisement, but in the
seeking of satisfaction for reasonable desire accompanied by
benevolence; whereas egoism is the preference of our own interests
to
those of others, self-respect merely puts us on an equal footing
with
our fellows. It is true that in the Discourse Rousseau is pleading
against the development of many human faculties; but he is equally
advocating the fullest development of those he regards as
"natural,"
by which he means merely "good." The "state of
society," as envisaged in the
Social Contract, is
no longer in contradiction to the "state of nature" upheld
in the Emile,
where indeed the social environment is of the greatest importance,
and, though the pupil is screened from it, he is none the less
being
trained for it. Indeed the views given in the
Social Contract are
summarised in the fifth book of the
Emile, and by this
summary the essential unity of Rousseau's system is
emphasised.Rousseau's
object, then, in the first words of the
Social Contract,
"is to inquire if, in the civil order, there can be any sure and
certain, rule of administration, taking men as they are and laws as
they might be." Montesquieu took laws as they were, and saw what
sort of men they made: Rousseau, founding his whole system on human
freedom, takes man as the basis, and regards him as giving himself
what laws he pleases. He takes his stand on the nature of human
freedom: on this he bases his whole system, making the will of the
members the sole basis of every society.In
working out his theory, Rousseau makes use throughout of three
general and, to some extent, alternative conceptions. These are the
Social Contract, Sovereignty and the General Will. We shall now
have
to examine each of these in turn.The
Social Contract theory is as old as the sophists of Greece (see
Plato, Republic,
Book II and the
Gorgias), and as I
elusive. It has been adapted to the most opposite points of view,
and
used, in different forms, on both sides of every question to which
it
could conceivably be applied. It is frequent in mediæval writers, a
commonplace with the theorists of the Renaissance, and in the
eighteenth century already nearing its fall before a wider
conception. It would be a long, as well as a thankless, task to
trace
its history over again: it may be followed best in D. G. Ritchie's
admirable essay on it in
Darwin and Hegel and Other Studies.
For us, it is important only to regard it in its most general
aspect,
before studying the special use made of it by Rousseau. Obviously,
in
one form or another, it is a theory very easily arrived at.
Wherever
any form of government apart from the merest tyranny exists,
reflection on the basis of the State cannot but lead to the notion
that, in one sense or another, it is based on the consent, tacit or
expressed, past or present, of its members. In this alone, the
greater part of the Social Contract theory is already latent. Add
the
desire to find actual justification for a theory in facts, and,
especially in an age possessed only of the haziest historical
sense,
this doctrine of consent will inevitably be given a historical
setting. If in addition there is a tendency to regard society as
something unnatural to humanity, the tendency will become
irresistible. By writers of almost all schools, the State will be
represented as having arisen, in some remote age, out of a compact
or, in more legal phrase, contract between two or more parties. The
only class that will be able to resist the doctrine is that which
maintains the divine right of kings, and holds that all existing
governments were were imposed on the people by the direct
interposition of God. All who are not prepared to maintain that
will
be partisans of some form or other of the Social Contract
theory.It
is, therefore, not surprising that we find among its advocates
writers of the most opposite points of view. Barely stated, it is a
mere formula, which may be filled in with any content from
absolutism
to pure republicanism. And, in the hands of some at least of its
supporters, it turns out to be a weapon that cuts both ways. We
shall
be in a better position to judge of its usefulness when we have
seen
its chief varieties at work.All
Social Contract theories that are at all definite fall under one or
other of two heads. They represent society as based on an original
contract either between the people and the government, or between
all
the individuals composing the State. Historically, modern theory
passes from the first to the second of these forms.The
doctrine that society is founded on a contract between the people
and
the government is of mediæval origin. It was often supported by
references to the Old Testament, which contains a similar view in
an
unreflective form. It is found in most of the great political
writers
of the sixteenth century; in Buchanan, and in the writings of James
I: it persists into the seventeenth in the works of Grotius and
Puffendorf. Grotius is sometimes held to have stated the theory so
as
to admit both forms of contract; but it is clear that he is only
thinking of the first form as admitting democratic as well as
monarchical government. We find it put very clearly by the
Convention
Parliament of 1688, which accuses James II of having "endeavoured
to subvert the constitution of the kingdom by breaking the original
contract between king and people." While Hobbes, on the side of
the royalists, is maintaining the contract theory in its second
form,
the Parliamentarian Algernon Sidney adheres to the idea of a
contract
between the people and the government.In
this form, the theory clearly admits of opposite interpretations.
It
may be held that the people, having given itself up once for all to
its rulers, has nothing more to ask of them, and is bound to submit
to any usage they may choose to inflict. This, however, is not the
implication most usually drawn from it. The theory, in this form,
originated with theologians who were also lawyers. Their view of a
contract implied mutual obligations; they regarded the ruler as
bound, by its terms, to govern constitutionally. The old idea that
a
king must not violate the sacred customs of the realm passes easily
into the doctrine that he must not violate the terms of the
original
contract between himself and his people. Just as in the days of the
Norman kings, every appeal on the part of the people for more
liberties was couched in the form of a demand that the customs of
the
"good old times" of Edward the Confessor should be
respected, so in the seventeenth century every act of popular
assertion or resistance was stated as an appeal to the king not to
violate the contract. The demand was a good popular cry, and it
seemed to have the theorists behind it. Rousseau gives his
refutation
of this view, which he had, in the
Discourse on Inequality,
maintained in passing, in the sixteenth chapter of the third book
of
the Social Contract.
(See also Book I, chap, iv, init.) His attack is really concerned
also with the theory of Hobbes, which in some respects resembles,
as
we shall see, this first view; but, in form at least, it is
directed
against this form of contract. It will be possible to examine it
more
closely, when the second view has been considered.The
second view, which may be called the Social Contract theory proper,
regards society as originating in, or based on, an agreement
between
the individuals composing it. It seems to be found first, rather
vaguely, in Richard Hooker's
Ecclesiastical Polity,
from which Locke largely borrowed: and it reappears, in varying
forms, in Milton's
Tenure of Kings and Magistrates,
in Hobbes's
Leviathan, in
Locke's Treatises on
Civil Government,
and in Rousseau. The best-known instance of its actual use is by
the
Pilgrim Fathers on the
Mayflower in 1620,
in whose declaration occurs the phrase, "We do solemnly and
mutually, in the presence of God and of one another, covenant and
combine ourselves together into a civil body politic." The
natural implication of this view would seem to be the corollary of
complete popular Sovereignty which Rousseau draws. But before
Rousseau's time it had been used to support views as diverse as
those
which rested on the first form. We saw that, in Grotius's great
work,
De Jure Belli et Pacis,
it was already possible to doubt which of the two theories was
being
advocated. The first theory was, historically, a means of popular
protest against royal aggression. As soon as popular government was
taken into account, the act of contract between people and
government
became in effect merely a contract between the individuals
composing
the society, and readily passed over into the second form.The
second theory, in its ordinary form, expresses only the view that
the
people is everywhere Sovereign, and that, in the phrase of Milton's
treatise, "the power of kings and magistrates is only
derivative." Before, however, this view had been worked up into
a philosophical theory, it had already been used by Hobbes to
support
precisely opposite principles. Hobbes agrees that the original
contract is one between all the individuals composing the State,
and
that the government is no party to it; but he regards the people as
agreeing, not merely to form a State, but to invest a certain
person
or certain persons with the government of it. He agrees that the
people is naturally supreme, but regards it as alienating its
Sovereignty by the contract itself, and delegating its power,
wholly
and for ever, to the government. As soon, therefore, as the State
is
set up, the government becomes for Hobbes the Sovereign; there is
no
more question of popular Sovereignty, but only of passive
obedience:
the people is bound, by the contract, to obey its ruler, no matter
whether he governs well or ill. It has alienated all its rights to
the Sovereign, who is, therefore, absolute master. Hobbes, living
in
a time of civil wars, regards the worst government as better than
anarchy, and is, therefore, at pains to find arguments in support
of
any form of absolutism. It is easy to pick holes in this system,
and
to see into what difficulties a conscientious Hobbist might be led
by
a revolution. For as soon as the revolutionaries get the upper
hand,
he will have to sacrifice one of his principles: he will have to
side
against either the actual or the legitimate Sovereign. It is easy
also to see that alienation of liberty, even if possible for an
individual, which Rousseau denies, cannot bind his posterity. But,
with all its faults, the view of Hobbes is on the whole admirably,
if
ruthlessly, logical, and to it Rousseau owes a great deal.The
special shape given to the second Social Contract theory by Hobbes
looks, at first sight, much like a combination, into a single act,
of
both the contracts. This, however, is not the view he adopts. The
theory of a contract between government and people had, as we have
seen, been used mainly as a support for popular liberties, a means
of
assertion against the government. Hobbes, whose whole aim is to
make
his government Sovereign, can only do this by leaving the
government
outside the contract: he thus avoids the necessity of submitting it
to any obligation whatsoever, and leaves it absolute and
irresponsible. He secures, in fact, not merely a State which has
unbounded rights against the individual, but a determinate
authority
with the right to enforce those rights. His theory is not merely
Statism (étatisme);
it is pure despotism.It
is clear that, if such a theory is to be upheld, it can stand only
by
the view, which Hobbes shares with Grotius, that a man can alienate
not merely his own liberty, but also that of his descendants, and
that, consequently, a people as a whole can do the same. This is
the
point at which both Locke and Rousseau attack it. Locke, whose aim
is
largely to justify the Revolution of 1688, makes government depend,
not merely at its institution, but always, on the consent of the
governed, and regards all rulers as liable to be displaced if they
govern tyrannically. He omits, however, to provide any machinery
short of revolution for the expression of popular opinion, and, on
the whole, seems to regard the popular consent as something
essentially tacit and assumed. He regards the State as existing
mainly to protect life and property, and is, in all his assertions
of
popular rights, so cautious as to reduce them almost to nothing. It
is not till we come to Rousseau that the second form of the
contract
theory is stated in its purest and most logical form.Rousseau
sees clearly the necessity, if popular consent in government is to
be
more than a name, of giving it some constitutional means of
expression. For Locke's theory of tacit consent, he substitutes an
active agreement periodically renewed. He looks back with
admiration
to the city-states of ancient Greece and, in his own day, reserves
his admiration for the Swiss free cities, Berne and, above all,
Geneva, his native place. Seeing in the Europe of his day no case
in
which representative government was working at all democratically,
he
was unable to conceive that means might be found of giving effect
to
this active agreement in a nation-state; he therefore held that
self-government was impossible except for a city. He wished to
break
up the nation-states of Europe, and create instead federative
leagues
of independent city-states.It
matters, however, comparatively little, for the appreciation of
Rousseau's political theory in general, that he failed to become
the
theorist of the modern State. By taking the State, which must have,
in essentials, everywhere the same basis, at its simplest, he was
able, far better than his predecessors, to bring out the real
nature
of the "social tie," an alternative name which he often
uses for the Social Contract. His doctrine I of the underlying
principle of political obligation is that of all great modern
writers, from Kant to Mr. Bosanquet. This fundamental unity has
been
obscured only because critics have failed to put the Social
Contract
theory in its proper place in Rousseau's system.This
theory was, we have seen, a commonplace. The amount of historical
authenticity assigned to the contract almost universally
presupposed
varied enormously. Generally, the weaker a writer's rational basis,
the more he appealed to history—and invented it. It was, therefore,
almost inevitable that Rousseau should cast his theory into the
contractual form. There were, indeed, writers of his time who
laughed
at the contract, but they were not writers who constructed a
general
system of political philosophy. From Cromwell to Montesquieu and
Bentham, it was the practically minded man, impatient of unactual
hypotheses, who refused to accept the idea of contract. The
theorists
were as unanimous in its favour as the Victorians were in favour of
the "organic" theory. But we, criticising them in the light
of later events, are in a better position for estimating the
position
the Social Contract really took in their political system. We see
that Locke's doctrine of tacit consent made popular control so
unreal
that he was forced, if the State was to have any hold, to make his
contract historical and actual, binding posterity for all time, and
that he was also led to admit a quasi-contract between people and
government, as a second vindication of popular liberties. Rousseau,
on the other hand, bases no vital argument on the historical nature
of the contract, in which, indeed, he clearly does not believe.
"How," he asks, "did this change [from nature to
society] come about?" And he answers that he does not know.
Moreover, his aim is to find "a sure and legitimate rule of
administration, taking men as they are and laws as they might be";
that is to say, his Social Contract is something which will be
found
at work in every legitimate society, but which will be in abeyance
in
all forms of despotism. He clearly means by it no more and no less
than the fundamental principle of political association, the basis
of
the unity which enables us, in the State, to realise political
liberty by giving up lawlessness and license. The presentation of
this doctrine in the quasi-historical form of the Social Contract
theory is due to the accident of the time and place in which
Rousseau
wrote. At the same time, the importance of the conception is best
to
be seen in the hard death it dies. Though no-one, for a hundred
years
or so, has thought of regarding it as historical, it has been found
so hard to secure any other phrase explaining as well or better the
basis of political union that, to this day, the phraseology of the
contract theory largely persists. A conception so vital cannot have
been barren.It
is indeed, in Rousseau's own thought, only one of the three
different
ways in which the basis of political union is stated, according to
the preoccupation of his mind. When he is thinking
quasi-historically, he describes his doctrine as that of the Social
Contract. Modern anthropology, in its attempts to explain the
complex
by means of the simple, often strays further from the straight
paths
of history and reason. In a semi-legal aspect, using the
terminology,
if not the standpoint, of jurisprudence, he restates the same
doctrine in the form of popular Sovereignty. This use tends
continually to pass over into the more philosophical form which
comes
third. "Sovereignty is the exercise of the general will."
Philosophically, Rousseau's doctrine finds its expression in the
view
that the State is based not on any original convention, not on, any
determinate power, but on the living and sustaining rational will
of
its members. We have now to examine first Sovereignty and then the
General Will, which is ultimately Rousseau's guiding
conception.Sovereignty
is, first and foremost, a legal term, and it has often been held
that
its use in political philosophy merely leads to confusion. In
jurisprudence, we are told, it has the perfectly plain meaning
given
to it in Austin's famous definition. The Sovereign is "a
determinate human
superior, not
in a habit of obedience to a like superior, but receiving
habitual obedience
from the bulk
of a given society." Where Sovereignty is placed is, on this
view, a question purely of fact, and never of right. We have only
to
seek out the determinate human superior in a given society, and we
shall have the Sovereign. In answer to this theory, it is not
enough,
though it is a valuable point, to show that such a determinate
superior is rarely to be found. Where, for instance, is the
Sovereign
of England or of the British Empire? Is it the King, who is called
the Sovereign? Or is it the Parliament, which is the legislature
(for
Austin's Sovereign is regarded as the source of law)? Or is it the
electorate, or the whole mass of the population, with or without
the
right of voting? Clearly all these exercise a certain influence in
the making of laws. Or finally, is it now the Cabinet? For Austin,
one of these bodies would be ruled out as indeterminate (the mass
of
the population) and another as responsible (the Cabinet). But are
we
to regard the House of Commons or those who elect it as forming
part
of the Sovereign? The search for a determinate Sovereign may be a
valuable legal conception; but it has evidently nothing to do with
political theory.It
is, therefore, essential to distinguish between the legal Sovereign
of jurisprudence, and the political Sovereign of political science
and philosophy. Even so, it does not at once become clear what this
political Sovereign may be. Is it the body or bodies of persons in
whom political power in a State actually resides? Is it merely the
complex of actual institutions regarded as embodying the will of
the
society? This would leave us still in the realm of mere fact,
outside
both right and philosophy. The Sovereign, in the philosophical
sense,
is neither the nominal Sovereign, nor the legal Sovereign, nor the
political Sovereign of fact and common sense: it is the consequence
of the fundamental bond of union, the restatement of the doctrine
of
Social Contract, the foreshadowing of that of General Will. The
Sovereign is that body in the State in which political
power ought always
to reside, and in which the
right to such power
does always reside.The
idea at the back of the philosophical conception of Sovereignty is,
therefore, essentially the same as that we found to underlie the
Social Contract theory. It is the view that the people, whether it
can alienate its right or not, is the ultimate director of its own
destinies, the final power from which there is no appeal. In a
sense,
this is recognised even by Hobbes, who makes the power of his
absolute Sovereign, the predecessor of Austin's "determinate
human superior," issue first of all from the Social Contract,
which is essentially a popular act. The difference between Hobbes
and
Rousseau on this point is solely that Rousseau regards as
inalienable
a supreme power which Hobbes makes the people alienate in its first
corporate action. That is to say, Hobbes in fact accepts the theory
of popular supremacy in name only to destroy it in fact; Rousseau
asserts the theory in its only logical form, and is under no
temptation to evade it by means of false historical assumptions. In
Locke, a distinction is already drawn between the legal and the
actual Sovereign, which Locke calls "supreme power";
Rousseau unites the absolute Sovereignty of Hobbes and the "popular
consent" of Locke into the philosophic doctrine of popular
Sovereignty, which has since been the established form of the
theory.
His final view represents a return from the perversions of Hobbes
to
a doctrine already familiar to mediæval and Renaissance writers;
but
it is not merely a return. In its passage the view has fallen into
its place in a complete system of political philosophy.In
a second important respect Rousseau differentiates himself from
Hobbes. For Hobbes, the Sovereign is identical with the government.
He is so hot for absolutism largely because he regards revolution,
the overthrow of the existing government, as at the same time the
dissolution of the body politic, and a return to complete anarchy
or
to the "state of nature." Rousseau and, to some extent,
Locke meet this view by sharp division between the supreme power
and
the government. For Rousseau, they are so clearly distinct that
even
a completely democratic government is not at the same time the
Sovereign; its members are sovereign only in a different capacity
and
as a different corporate body, just as two different societies may
exist for different purposes with exactly the same members. Pure
democracy, however, the government of the State by all the people
in
every detail, is not, as Rousseau says, a possible human
institution.
All governments are really
mixed in character;
and what we call a democracy is only a more or less democratic
government. Government, therefore, will always be to some extent in
the hands of selected persons. Sovereignty, on the other hand, is
in
his view absolute, inalienable, indivisible, and indestructible. It
cannot be limited, abandoned, shared or destroyed. It is an
essential
part of all social life that the right to control the destinies of
the State belongs in the last resort to the whole people. There
clearly must in the end be somewhere in the society an ultimate
court
of appeal, whether determinate or not; but, unless Sovereignty is
distinguished from government, the government, passing under the
name
of Sovereign, will inevitably be regarded as absolute. The only way
to avoid the conclusions of Hobbes is, therefore, to establish a
clear separation between them.Rousseau
tries to do this by an adaptation of the doctrine of the "three
powers." But instead of three independent powers sharing the
supreme authority, he gives only two, and makes one of these wholly
dependent on the other. He substitutes for the co-ordination of the
legislative, the executive, and the judicial authorities, a system
in
which the legislative power, or Sovereign, is always supreme, the
executive, or government, always secondary and derivative, and the
judicial power merely a function of government. This division he
makes, naturally, one of
will and
power. The
government is merely to carry out the decrees, or acts of will, of
the Sovereign people. Just as the human will transfers a command to
its members for execution, so the body politic may give its
decisions
force by setting up authority which, like the brain, may command
its
members. In delegating the power necessary for the execution of its
will, it is abandoning none of its supreme authority. It remains
Sovereign, and can at any moment recall the grants it has made.
Government, therefore, exists only at the Sovereign's pleasure, and
is always revocable by the sovereign will.It
will be seen, when we come to discuss the nature of the General
Will,
that this doctrine really contains the most valuable part of
Rousseau's theory. Here, we are concerned rather with its
limitations. The distinction between legislative and executive
functions is in practice very hard to draw. In Rousseau's case, it
is
further complicated by the presence of a second distinction. The
legislative power, the Sovereign, is concerned only with what is
general, the executive only with what is particular. This
distinction, the full force of which can only be seen in connection
with the General Will, means roughly that a matter is general when
it
concerns the whole community equally, and makes no mention of any
particular class; as soon as it refers to any class or person, it
becomes particular, and can no longer form the subject matter of an
act of Sovereignty. However just this distinction may seem in the
abstract, it is clear that its effect is to place all the power in
the hands of the executive: modern legislation is almost always
concerned with particular classes and interests. It is not,
therefore, a long step from the view of Rousseau to the modern
theory
of democratic government, in which the people has little power
beyond
that of removing its rulers if they displease it. As long, however,
as we confine our view to the city-state of which Rousseau is
thinking, his distinction is capable of preserving for the people a
greater actual exercise of will. A city can often generalise where
a
nation must particularise.It
is in the third book of the
Social Contract,
where Rousseau is discussing the problem of government, that it is
most essential to remember that his discussion has in view mainly
the
city-state and not the nation. Broadly put, his principle of
government is that democracy is possible only in small States,
aristocracy in those of medium extent, and monarchy in great States
(Book III, chap. iii). In considering this view, we have to take
into
account two things. First, he rejects representative government;
will
being, in his theory, inalienable, representative Sovereignty is
impossible. But, as he regards all general acts as functions of
Sovereignty, this means that no general act can be within the
competence of a representative assembly. In judging this theory, we
must take into account all the circumstances of Rousseau's time.
France, Geneva and England were the three States he took most into
account. In France, representative government was practically
non-existent; in Geneva, it was only partially necessary; in
England,
it was a mockery, used to support a corrupt oligarchy against a
debased monarchy. Rousseau may well be pardoned for not taking the
ordinary modern view of it. Nor indeed is it, even in the modern
world, so satisfactory an instrument of the popular will that we
can
afford wholly to discard his criticism. It is one of the problems
of
the day to find some means of securing effective popular control
over
a weakened Parliament and a despotic Cabinet.The
second factor is the immense development of local government. It
seemed to Rousseau that, in the nation-state, all authority must
necessarily pass, as it had in France, to the central power.
Devolution was hardly dreamed of; and Rousseau saw the only means
of
securing effective popular government in a federal system, starting
from the small unit as Sovereign. The nineteenth century has proved
the falsehood of much of his theory of government; but there are
still many wise comments and fruitful suggestions to be found in
the
third book of the
Social Contract and
in the treatise on the
Government of Poland,
as well as in his adaptation and criticism of the
Polysynodie of the
Abbé de Saint-Pierre, a scheme of local government for France, born
out of its due time.The
point in Rousseau's theory of Sovereignty that offers most
difficulty
is his view (Book II, chap, vii) that, for every State, a
Legislator is
necessary. We shall understand the section only by realising that
the
legislator is, in fact, in Rousseau's system, the spirit of
institutions personified; his place, in a developed society, is
taken
by the whole complex of social custom, organisation and tradition
that has grown up with the State. This is made clearer by the fact
that the legislator is not to exercise legislative power; he is
merely to submit his suggestions for popular approval. Thus
Rousseau
recognises that, in the case of institutions and traditions as
elsewhere, will, and not force, is the basis of the State.This
may be seen in his treatment of law as a whole (Book II, chap, vi),
which deserves very careful attention. He defines laws as "acts
of the general will," and, agreeing with Montesquieu in making
law the "condition of civil association," goes beyond him
only in tracing it more definitely to its origin in an act of will.
The Social Contract renders law necessary, and at the same time
makes
it quite clear that laws can proceed only from the body of citizens
who have constituted the State. "Doubtless," says Rousseau,
"there is a universal justice emanating from reason alone; but
this justice, to be admitted among us, must be mutual. Humbly
speaking, in default of natural sanctions, the laws of justice are
ineffective among men." Of the law which set up among men this
reign of mutual justice the General Will is the source.We
thus come at last to the General Will, the most disputed, and
certainly the most fundamental, of all Rousseau's political
concepts.
No critic of the
Social Contract has
found it easy to say either what precisely its author meant by it,
or
what is its final value for political philosophy. The difficulty is
increased because Rousseau himself sometimes halts in the sense
which
he assigns to it, and even seems to suggest by it two different
ideas. Of its broad meaning, however, there can be no doubt. The
effect of the Social Contract is the creation of a new individual.
When it has taken place, "at once, in place of the individual
personality of each contracting party, the act of association
creates
a moral and collective body, composed of as many members as the
assembly contains voters, and receiving from the act its unity, its
common identity (moi
commun), its life
and its will" (Book I, chap. vi). The same doctrine had been
stated earlier, in the
Political Economy,
without the historical setting. "The body politic is also a
moral being, possessed of a will, and this general will, which
tends
always to the preservation and welfare of the whole and of every
part, and is the source of the laws, constitutes for all the
members
of the State, in their relations to one another and to it, the rule
of what is just or unjust." It will be seen at once that the
second statement, which could easily be fortified by others from
the
Social Contract,
says more than the first. It is not apparent that the common will,
created by the institution of society, need "tend always to the
welfare of the whole." Is not the common will at least as
fallible as the will of a single individual? May it not equally be
led away from its true interests to the pursuit of pleasure or of
something which is really harmful to it? And, if the whole society
may vote what conduces to the momentary pleasure of all the members
and at the same time to the lasting damage of the State as a whole,
is it not still more likely that some of the members will try to
secure their private interests in opposition to those of the whole
and of others? All these questions, and others like them, have been
asked by critics of the conception of the General Will.Two
main points are involved, to one of which Rousseau gives a clear
and
definite answer. "There is often," he says, "a great
deal of difference between the
will of all and the
general will; the
latter takes account only of the common interest, while the former
takes private interest into account, and is no more than a sum of
particular wills." "The agreement of all interests is
formed by opposition to that of each" (Book II, chap. iii). It
is indeed possible for a citizen, when an issue is presented to
him,
to vote not for the good of the State, but for his own good; but,
in
such a case, his vote, from the point of view of the General Will,
is
merely negligible. But "does it follow that the general will is
exterminated or corrupted? Not at all: it is always constant,
unalterable, and pure; but it is subordinated to other wills which
encroach upon its sphere.... The fault [each man] commits [in
detaching his interest from the common interest] is that of
changing
the state of the question, and answering something different from
what he is asked. Instead of saying by his vote 'It is to the
advantage of the State,' he says, 'It is to the advantage of this
or
that man or party that this or that view should prevail.' Thus the
law of public order in assemblies is not so much to maintain in
them
the general will as to secure that the question be always put to
it,
and the answer always given by it" (Book IV, chap. i). These
passages, with many others that may be found in the text, make it
quite clear that by the General Will Rousseau means something quite
distinct from the Will of All, with which it should never have been
confused. The only excuse for such confusion lies in his view that
when, in a
city-state, all
particular associations are avoided, votes guided by individual
self-interest will always cancel one another, so that majority
voting
will always result in the General Will. This is clearly not the
case,
and in this respect we may charge him with pushing the democratic
argument too far. The point, however, can be better dealt with at a
later stage. Rousseau makes no pretence that the mere voice of a
majority is infallible; he only says, at the most, that, given his
ideal conditions, it would be so.The
second main point raised by critics of the General Will is whether
in
defining it as a will directed solely to the common interest,
Rousseau means to exclude acts of public immorality and
short-sightedness. He answers the questions in different ways.
First,
an act of public immorality would be merely an unanimous instance
of
selfishness, different in no particular, from similar acts less
unanimous, and therefore forming no part of a General Will.
Secondly,
a mere ignorance of our own and the State's good, entirely
unprompted
by selfish desires, does not make our will anti-social or
individual.
"The general will is always right and tends to the public
advantage; but it does not follow that the deliberations of the
people are always equally correct. Our will is always for our own
good, but we do not always see what that is: the people is never
corrupted, but it is often deceived, and on such occasions only
does
it seem to will what is bad" (Book II, chap. iii). It is
impossible to acquit Rousseau in some of the passages in which he
treats of the General Will, of something worse than
obscurity—positive contradiction. It is probable, indeed, that he
never quite succeeded in getting his view clear in his own mind;
there is nearly always, in his treatment of it, a certain amount of
muddle and fluctuation. These difficulties the student must be left
to worry out for himself; it is only possible to present, in
outline,
what Rousseau meant to convey.The
treatment of the General Will in the
Political Economy
is brief and lucid, and furnishes the best guide to his meaning.
The
definition of it in this work, which has already been quoted, is
followed by a short account of the nature of
general wills as a
whole. "Every political society is composed of other smaller
societies of various kinds, each of which has its interest and
rules
of conduct; but those societies which everybody perceives, because
they have an external or authorised form, are not the only ones
that
actually exist in the State: all individuals who are united by a
common interest compose as many others, either temporary or
permanent, whose influence is none the less real because it is less
apparent.... The influence of all these tacit or formal
associations
causes by the influence of their will as many modifications of the
public will. The will of these particular societies has always two
relations; for the members of the association, it is a general
will;
for the great society, it is a particular will; and it is often
right
with regard to the first object and wrong as to the second. The
most
general will is always the most just, and the voice of the people
is,
in fact, the voice of God."The
General Will, Rousseau continues in substance, is always for the
common good; but it is sometimes divided into smaller general
wills,
which are wrong in relation to it. The supremacy of the great
General
Will is "the first principle of public economy and the
fundamental rule of government." In this passage, which differs
only in clearness and simplicity from others in the
Social Contract
itself, it is easy to see how far Rousseau had in his mind a
perfectly definite idea. Every association of several persons
creates
a new common will; every association of a permanent character has
already a "personality" of its own, and in consequence a
"general" will; the State, the highest known form of
association, is a fully developed moral and collective being with a
common will which is, in the highest sense yet known to us,
general.
All such wills are general only for the members of the associations
Which exercise them; for outsiders, or rather for other
associations,
they are purely particular wills. This applies even to the State;
"for, in relation to what is outside it, the State becomes a
simple being, an individual" (Social
Contract, Book I.
chap. vii). In certain passages in the
Social Contract, in
his criticism of the Abbé de Saint-Pierre's
Project of Perpetual Peace,
and in the second chapter of the original draft of the
Social Contract,
Rousseau takes into account the possibility of a still higher
individual, "the federation of the world." In the
Political Economy,
thinking of the nation-state, he affirms what in the