Introduction to the Philosophy and Writings of Plato
Introduction to the Philosophy and Writings of PlatoINTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY AND WRITINGS OF PLATOEXPLANATIONS OF CERTAIN PLATONIC TERMSCopyright
Introduction to the Philosophy and Writings of Plato
Thomas Taylor
INTRODUCTION TO THE PHILOSOPHY AND WRITINGS OF PLATO
"Philosophy," says Hierocles, "is the purification and
perfection of human life. It is the purification, indeed, from
material irrationality, and the mortal body; but the perfection, in
consequence of being the resumption of our proper felicity, and a
reascent to the divine likeness. To effect these two is the
province of Virtue and Truth; the former exterminating the
immoderation of the passions; and the latter introducing the divine
form to those who are naturally adapted to its
reception."Of philosophy thus defined, which may be compared to a
luminous pyramid, terminating in Deity, and having for its basis
the rational soul of man and its spontaneous unperverted
conceptions,—of this philosophy, August, magnificent, and divine,
Plato may be justly called the primary leader and hierophant,
through whom, like the mystic light in the inmost recesses of some
sacred temple, it first shone forth with occult and venerable
splendour.[1] It may indeed be truly said of the whole of this
philosophy, that it is the greatest good which man can participate:
for if it purifies us from the defilements of the passions and
assimilates us to Divinity, it confers on us the proper felicity of
our nature. Hence it is easy to collect its pre-eminence to all
other philosophies; to show that where they oppose it, they are
erroneous; that so far as they contain any thing scientific they
are allied to it; and that at best they are but rivulets derived
from this vast ocean of truth.[1] In the mysteries a light of this kind shone forth
from the adytum of the temple in which they were
exhibited.
To evince that the philosophy of Plato possesses this preeminence;
that its dignity and sublimity are unrivaled; that it is the parent
of all that ennobles man; and, that it is founded on principles,
which neither time can obliterate, nor sophistry subvert, is the
principal design of this Introduction.To effect this design, I shall in the first place present the
reader with the outlines of the principal dogmas of Plato's
philosophy. The undertaking is indeed no less novel than arduous,
since the author of it has to tread in paths which have been
untrodden for upwards of a thousand years, and to bring to light
truths which for that extended period have been concealed in Greek.
Let not the reader, therefore, be surprised at the solitariness of
the paths through which I shall attempt to conduct him, or at the
novelty of the objects which will present themselves in the
journey: for perhaps he may fortunately recollect that he has
traveled the same road before, that the scenes were once familiar
to him, and that the country through which he is passing is his
native land. At, least, if his sight should be dim, and his memory
oblivious, (for the objects which he will meet with can only be
seen by the most piercing eyes,) and his absence from them has been
lamentably long, let him implore the power of wisdom,From mortal mists to purify his
eyes, That God and man he may distinctly
see.Let us also, imploring the assistance of the same
illuminating power, begin the solitary journey.Of all the dogmas of Plato, that concerning the first
principle of things as far transcends in sublimity the doctrine of
other philosophers of a different sect, on this subject, as this
supreme cause of all transcends other causes. For, according to
Plato, the highest God, whom in the Republic he calls the good, and
in the Parmenides the one, is not only above soul and intellect,
but is even superior to being itself. Hence, since every thing
which can in any respect be known, or of which any thing can be
asserted, must be connected with the universality of things, but
the first cause is above all things, it is very properly said by
Plato to be perfectly ineffable. The first hypothesis therefore of
his, Parmenides, in which all things are denied of this immense
principle, concludes as follows: "The one therefore is in no
respect. So it seems. Hence it is not in such a manner as to be
one, for thus it would be being, and participate of essence; but as
it appears, the one neither is one, nor is, if it be proper to
believe in reasoning of this kind. It appears so. But can any thing
either belong to, or be affirmed of that, which is not? How can it?
Neither therefore does any name belong to it, nor discourse, nor
any science, nor sense, nor opinion. It does not appear that there
can. Hence it can neither be named, nor spoken of, nor conceived by
opinion, nor be known, nor perceived by any being. So it seems."
And here it must be observed that this conclusion respecting the
highest principle of things, that he is perfectly ineffable and
inconceivable, is the result of a most scientific series of
negations, in which not only all sensible and intellectual beings
are denied of him, but even natures the most transcendently allied
to him, his first and most divine progeny. For that which so
eminently distinguishes the philosophy of Plato from others is
this, that every part of it is stamped with the character of
science. The vulgar indeed proclaim the Deity to be ineffable; but
as they have no scientific knowledge that he is so, this is nothing
more than a confused and indistinct perception of the most sublime
of all truths, like that of a thing seen between sleeping and
waking, like Phaeacia to Ulysses when sailing to his native
land,That lay before him indistinct and
vast, Like a broad shield amid the watr'y
waste.In short, an unscientific perception of the ineffable nature
of the Divinity resembles that of a man, who on surveying the
heavens, should assert of the altitude of its highest part, that it
surpasses that of the loftiest tree, and is therefore immeasurable.
But to see this scientifically, is like a survey of this highest
part of the heavens by the astronomer; for he by knowing the height
of the media between us and it, knows also scientifically that it
transcends in altitude not only the loftiest tree; but the summits
of air and aether, the moon, and even the sun itself.Let us therefore investigate what is the ascent to the
ineffably, and after what manner it is accomplished, according to
Plato, from the last of things, following the profound and most
inquisitive Damascius as our leader in this arduous investigation.
Let our discourse also be common to other principles, and to things
proceeding from them to that which is last, and let us, beginning
from that which is perfectly effable and known to sense, ascend too
the ineffable, and establish in silence, as in a port, the
parturitions of truth concerning it. Let us then assume the
following axiom, in which as in a secure vehicle we may safely pass
from hence thither. I say, therefore, that the unindigent is
naturally prior to the indigent. For that which is in want of
another is naturally adapted from necessity to be subservient to
that of which it is indigent. But if they are mutually in want of
each other, each being indigent of the other in a different
respect, neither of them will be the principle. For the unindigent
is most adapted to that which is truly the principle. And if it is
in want of any thing, according to this it will not be the
principle. It is however necessary that the principles should be
this very thing, the principle alone. The unindigent therefore
pertains to this, nor must it by any means be acknowledged that
there is any thing prior to it. This however, would be acknowledged
if it had any connection with the indigent.Let us then consider body, (that is, a triply extended
substance,) endued with quality; for this is the first thing
effable by us, and is, sensible. Is this then the principle of
things? But it is two things, body, and quality which is in body as
a subject. Which of these therefore is by nature prior? For both
are indigent of their proper parts; and that also which is in a
subject is indigent of the subject. Shall we say then that body
itself is the principle of the first essence? But this is
impossible. For, in the first place, the principle will not receive
any thing from that which is posterior to itself. But body, we say
is the recipient of quality. Hence quality, and a subsistence in
conjunction with it, are not derived from body, since quality is
present with body as something different. And, in the second place,
body is every way, divisible; its several parts are indigent of
each other, and the whole is indigent of all the parts. As it is
indigent, therefore, and receives its completion from things which
are indigent, it will not be entirely unindigent.Further still, if it is not one but united, it will require,
as Plato says, the connecting one. It is likewise something common
and formless, being as it were a certain matter. It requires,
therefore, ornament and the possession of form, that it may not be
merely body, but a body with a certain particular quality; as for
instance, a fiery, or earthly, body, and, in short, body adorned
and invested with a particular quality. Hence the things which
accede to it, finish and adorn it. Is then that which accedes the
principle? But this is impossible. For it does not abide in itself,
nor does it subsist alone, but is in a subject of which also it is
indigent. If, however, some one should assert that body is not a
subject, but one of the elements in each, as for instance, animal
in horses and man, thus also each will be indigent of the other,
viz. this subject, and that which is in the subject; or rather the
common element, animal, and the peculiarities, as the rational and
irrational, will be indigent. For elements are always, indigent of
each other, and that which is composed from elements is indigent of
the elements. In short, this sensible nature, and which is so
manifest to us, is neither body, for this does not of itself move
the senses, nor quality; for this does not possess an interval
commensurate with sense. Hence, that which is the object of sight,
is neither body nor color; but colored body, or color corporalized,
is that which is motive of the sight. And universally, that which
its sensible, which is body with a particular quality, is motive of
sense. From hence it is evident that the thing which excites the
sense is something incorporeal. For if it was body, it would not
yet be the object of sense. Body therefore requires that which is
incorporeal, and that which is incorporeal, body. For an
incorporeal nature, is not of itself sensible. It is, however,
different from body, because these two possess prerogatives
different from each other, and neither of these subsists prior to
the other; but being elements of one sensible thing, they are
present with each other; the one imparting interval to that which
is void of interval, but the other introducing to that which is
formless, sensible variety invested with form. In the third place,
neither are both these together the principles; since they are not
unindigent. For they stand in need of their proper elements, and of
that which conducts them to the generation of one form. For body
cannot effect this, since it is of itself impotent; nor quality,
since it is not able to subsist separate from the body in which it
is, or together with which it has its being. The composite
therefore either produces itself, which is impossible, for it does
not converge to itself, but the whole of it is multifariously
dispersed, or it is not produced by itself, and there is some other
principle prior to it.Let it then be supposed to be that which is called nature,
being a principle of motion and rest, in that which is moved and at
rest, essentially and not according to accident. For this is
something more simple, and is fabricative of composite forms. If,
however, it is in the things fabricated, and does not subsist
separate from nor prior to them, but stands in need of them for its
being, it will not be unindigent; though its possesses something
transcendent with respect to them, viz. the power of fashioning and
fabricating them. For it has its being together with them, and has
in them an inseparable subsistence; so that, when they are it is,
and is not when they are not, and this in consequence of perfectly
verging to them, and not being able to sustain that which is
appropriate. For the power of increasing, nourishing, and
generating similars, and the one prior to these three, viz. nature,
is not wholly incorporeal, but is nearly a certain quality of body,
from which it alone differs, in that it imparts to the composite to
be inwardly moved and at rest. For the quality of that which is
sensible imparts that which is apparent in matter, and that which
falls on sense. But body imparts interval every way extended; and
nature, an inwardly proceeding natural energy, whether according to
place only, or according to nourishing, increasing, and generating
things similar. Nature, however, is inseparable from a subject, and
is indigent, so that it will not be in short the principle, since
it is indigent of that which is subordinate. For it will not be
wonderful, if being a certain principle, it is indigent of the
principle above it; but it would be wonderful if it were indigent
of things posterior to itself, and of which it is supposed to be
the principle.By the like arguments we may show that the principle cannot
be irrational soul, whether sensitive, or orectic. For if it
appears that it has something separate, together with impulsive and
Gnostic enemies, yet at the same time it is bound in body, and has
something inseparable from it; since it is notable to convert
itself to itself, but its enemy is mingled with its subject. For it
is evident that its essence is something of this kind; since if it
were liberated and in itself free, it would also evince a certain
independent enemy, and would not always be converted to body; but
sometimes it would be converted to itself; or though it were always
converted to body, yet it would judge and explore itself. The
energies, therefore, of the multitude of mankind, (though they are
conversant with externals,) yet, at the same time they exhibit that
which is separate about them. For they consult how they should
engage in them, and observe that deliberation is necessary, in
order to effect or be passive to apparent good, or to decline
something of the contrary. But the impulses of other animals are
uniform and spontaneous, are moved together with the sensible
organs, and require the senses alone that they may obtain from
sensibles the pleasurable, and avoid the painful. If, therefore,
the body communicates in pleasure and pain, and is affected in a
certain respect by them, it is evident that the psychical energies,
(i.e. energies belonging to the soul) are exerted, mingled with
bodies, and are not purely psychical, but are also corporeal; for
perception is of the animated body, or of the soul corporalized,
though in such perception the psychical idiom predominates over the
corporeal; just as in bodies, the corporeal idiom has dominion
according to interval and subsistence. As the irrational soul,
therefore, has its being in something different from itself, so far
it is indigent of the subordinate: but a thing of this kind will
not be the principle.Prior them to this essence, we see a certain form separate
from a subject, and converted to itself, such as is the rational
nature. Our soul, therefore, presides over its proper energies and
corrects itself. This, however, would not be the case, unless it
was converted to itself; and it would not be converted, to itself
unless it had a separate essence. It is not therefore indigent of
the subordinate. Shall we then say that it is the most perfect
principle? But, it does not at once exert all its energies, but is
always indigent of the greater part. The principle, however, wishes
to have nothing indigent: but the rational nature is an essence in
want of its own energies. Some one, however, may say that it is an
eternal essence, and has never-failing essential energies, always
concurring with its essence, according to the self-moved and ever
vital, and that it is therefore unindigent; but the principle is
perfectly unindigent. Soul therefore, and which exerts mutable
energies, will not be the most proper principle. Hence it is
necessary that there should be something prior to this, which is in
every respect immutable, according to nature, life, and knowledge,
and according to all powers and enemies, such as we assert an
eternal and immutable essence to be, and such as is much honoured
intellect, to which Aristotle having ascended, thought he had
discovered the first principle. For what can be wanting to that
which perfectly comprehends in itself its own plenitudes
(oleromata), and of which neither addition nor ablation changes any
thing belonging to it? Or is not this also, one and many, whole and
parts, containing in itself, things first, middle, and last? The
subordinate plenitudes also stand in need of the more excellent,
and the more excellent of the subordinate, and the whole of the
parts. For the things related are indigent of each other, and what
are first of what are last, through the same cause; for it is not
of itself that which is first. Besides, the one here is indigent of
the many, because it has its subsistence in the many. Or it may be
said, that this one is collective of the many, and this not by
itself, but in conjunction with them. Hence there is much of the
indigent in this principle. For since intellect generates in itself
its proper plenitudes from which the whole at once receives its
completion, it will be itself indigent of itself, not only that
which is generated of that which generates, but also that which
generates, of that which is generated, in order to the whole
completion of that which wholly generates itself. Further still,
intellect understands and is understood, is intellective of and
intelligible to itself, and both these. Hence the intellectual is
indigent of the intelligible, as of its proper object of desire;
and the intelligible is in want of the intellectual, because it
wishes to be the intelligible of it. Both also are indigent of
either, since the possession is always accompanied with indigence,
in the same manner as the world is always present with matter.
Hence a certain indigence is naturally coessentiallized with
intellect, so that it cannot be the most proper principle. Shall
we, therefore, in the next place, direct our attention to the most
simple of beings, which Plato calls the one being, [Greek: en on]?
For as there is no separation there throughout the Whole, nor any
multitude, or order, or duplicity, or conversion to itself, what
indigence will there appear to me, in the perfectly united? And
especially what indigence will there be of that which is
subordinate? Hence the great Parmenides ascended to this most safe
principle, as that which is most unindigent. Is it not, however,
here necessary to attend to the conception of Plato, that the
united is not the one itself, but that which is passive[2] to it?
And this being the case, it is evident that it ranks after the one;
for it is supposed to be the united and not the one itself. If also
being is composed from the elements bound and infinity, as appears
from the Philebus of Plato, where he calls it that which is mixt,
it will be indigent of its elements. Besides, if the conception of
being is different from that of being united, and that which is a
whole is both united and being, these will be indigent of each
other, and the whole which is called one being is indigent of the
two. And though the one in this is better than being, yet this is
indigent of being, in order to the subsistence of one being. But if
being here supervenes the one, as it were, form in that which is
mixt and united, just as the idiom of man in that which is
collectively rational-mortal-animal, thus also the one will be
indigent of being. If, however, to speak more properly, the one is
two-fold; this being the cause of the mixture, and subsisting prior
to being, but that conferring rectitude, on being,—if this be the
case, neither will the indigent perfectly desert this nature. After
all these, it may be said that the one will be perfectly
unindigent. For neither is it indigent of that which is posterior
to itself for its subsistence, since the truly one is by itself
separated from all things; nor is it indigent of that which is
inferior or more excellent in itself; for there is nothing in it
besides itself; nor is it in want of itself. But it is one, because
neither has it any duplicity with respect to itself. For not even
the relation of itself to itself must be asserted of the truly one;
since it is perfectly simple. This, therefore, is the most
unindigent of all things. Hence this is the principle and the cause
of all; and this is at once the first of all things. If these
qualities, however, are present with it, it will not be the one. Or
may we not say that all things subsist in the one according to the
one? And that both these subsist in it, and such other things as we
predicate of it, as, for instance, the most simple, the most
excellent, the most powerful, the preserver of all things, and the
good itself? If these things, however, are thus true of the one, it
will thus also be indigent of things posterior to itself, according
to those very things which we add to it. For the principle is, and
is said to be the principle of things proceeding from it, and the
cause is the cause of things caused, and the first is the first of
things arranged, posterior to it.[3][2] See the Sophista of Plato, where this is
asserted.[3] For a thing cannot be
said to be a principle or cause without the subsistence of the
things of which it is the principle or cause. Hence, so far as it
is a principle or cause, it will be indigent of the subsistence of
these.