18,99 €
We are inclined to assume that digital technologies have suddenly revolutionized everything – including our relationships, our forms of work and leisure, and even our democracies – in just a few years. Armin Nassehi puts forward a new theory of digital society that turns this assumption on its head. Rather than treating digital technologies as an independent causal force that is transforming social life, he asks: what problem does digitalization solve?
When we pose the question in this way, we can see, argues Nassehi, that digitalization helps societies to deal with and reduce complexity by using coded numbers to process information. We can also see that modern societies had a digital structure long before computer technologies were developed – already in the nineteenth century, for example, statistical pattern recognition technologies were being used in functionally differentiated societies in order to recognize, monitor and control forms of human behaviour. Digital technologies were so successful in such a short period of time and were able to penetrate so many areas of society so quickly precisely because of a pre-existing sensitivity that prepared modern societies for digital development.
This highly original book lays the foundations for a theory of the digital society that will be of value to everyone interested in the growing presence of digital technologies in our lives.
Sie lesen das E-Book in den Legimi-Apps auf:
Seitenzahl: 611
Cover
Title Page
Copyright Page
Preface to the German edition
Preface to the English edition
Introduction
How to think about digitalization
A technological–sociological intuition
Early technology pushes
Original and copy
Productively wrong and predetermined breaking point
Notes
1. The Reference Problem of Digitalization
Functionalist questions
Connecting data: offline
What is the problem?
The discomfort with digital culture
The digital discovery of ‘society’
Empirical social research as pattern recognition
‘Society’ as digitalization material
The cyborg as a means of overcoming society?
Notes
2. The Idiosyncrasy of the Digital
The inexact exactness of the world
The particular idiosyncrasy of data
Cybernetics and the feedback of information
The digitalization of communication
The dynamic of closure
The self-referentiality of the data world
Notes
3. Multiple Duplications of the World
Data as observers
Duplications
Disruptions
Transverse data-like duplications
The trace of the trace and discrete duplications
Traces, patterns, networks
Notes
4. Simplicity and Diversity
Medium and form
Coding and programming
The digital simplicity of society
Increased options
Sapere aude
– dare to know – as reflected in digitalization
Notes
Excursus: Digital Metabolism
Notes
5. Functioning Technology
The function of the technological
Digital technology
Communicating technology
The function of functioning
Low-level technology
Demonized technology
Invisible technology and the Turing test
The privilege of making mistakes
Notes
6. Learning Technology
Decisions
Abductive machines?
Distributed intelligence?
Anthropological and technological questions
Experiencing and acting machines
Incompleteness, temporariness, systemic paradoxes
Artificial, bodily, and incomplete intelligence
Notes
7. The Internet as Mass Media
Surplus of meaning businesses
The function of synchronization
Synchronization and socialization
Selectivity, mediality, and voice on the Internet
Watching the watching
Complexity and overheating
The Internet as an archive of all possible statements
Intelligence in the mode of Future 2.0
Notes
8. Endangered Privacy
The improbability of informational self-determination
A new structural change in the public sphere?
Hazards
Privacy 1.0
Privacy 1.0 as a result of big data?
Big data and Privacy 2.0
Rescuing privacy?
Notes
9. Debug: Sociology Reborn from the Spirit of Digitalization
Digital dynamic and social complexity
An opportunity for sociology
Notes
Index
End User License Agreement
Cover
Table of Contents
Begin Reading
iii
iv
ix
x
xi
xii
1
2
3
4
5
6
7
8
9
10
11
12
13
14
15
16
17
18
19
20
21
22
23
24
25
26
27
28
29
30
31
32
33
34
35
36
37
38
39
40
41
42
43
44
45
46
47
48
49
50
51
52
53
54
55
56
57
58
59
60
61
62
63
64
65
66
67
68
69
70
71
72
73
74
75
76
77
78
79
80
81
82
83
84
85
86
87
88
89
90
91
92
93
94
95
96
97
98
99
100
101
102
103
104
105
106
107
108
109
110
111
112
113
114
115
116
117
118
119
120
121
122
123
124
125
126
127
128
129
130
131
132
133
134
135
136
137
138
139
140
141
142
143
144
145
146
147
148
149
150
151
152
153
154
155
156
157
159
158
160
161
162
163
164
165
166
167
168
169
170
171
172
173
174
175
176
177
178
179
180
181
182
183
184
185
186
187
188
189
190
191
192
193
194
195
196
197
198
199
200
201
202
203
204
205
206
207
208
209
210
211
212
213
214
215
216
217
218
219
220
221
222
223
224
225
226
227
228
229
230
231
232
233
234
235
236
237
238
239
259
260
261
262
263
264
265
266
267
268
269
270
271
Armin Nassehi
Translated by Mirko Wittwar
polity
Originally published in German as Muster. Theorie der digitalen Gesellschaft © Verlag C. H. Beck oHG, München 2021
This English edition © Polity Press, 2024
Vera Molnar, Hypertransformation, 74.338, 1974 © ADAGP, Paris and DACS, London 2023.
Vera Molnar, Aleatory Division of 4 Elements, 1959 © ADAGP, Paris and DACS, London 2023.
The translation of this book was made possible through funding from the Fritz Thyssen Foundation, Cologne.
Polity Press
65 Bridge Street
Cambridge CB2 1UR, UK
Polity Press
111 River Street
Hoboken, NJ 07030, USA
All rights reserved. Except for the quotation of short passages for the purpose of criticism and review, no part of this publication may be reproduced, stored in a retrieval system or transmitted, in any form or by any means, electronic, mechanical, photocopying, recording or otherwise, without the prior permission of the publisher.
ISBN-13: 978-1-5095-5821-6 (hardback)
ISBN-13: 978-1-5095-5822-3 (paperback)
A catalogue record for this book is available from the British Library.
Library of Congress Control Number: 2023936983
by Fakenham Prepress Solutions, Fakenham, Norfolk NR21 8NL
The publisher has used its best endeavours to ensure that the URLs for external websites referred to in this book are correct and active at the time of going to press. However, the publisher has no responsibility for the websites and can make no guarantee that a site will remain live or that the content is or will remain appropriate.
Every effort has been made to trace all copyright holders, but if any have been overlooked the publisher will be pleased to include any necessary credits in any subsequent reprint or edition.
For further information on Polity, visit our website: politybooks.com
I wrote this book in the winter of 2018/19. The manuscript was completed in April 2019. It makes the somewhat presumptuous attempt to fill in a gap, namely to think beyond the consequences of digitalization in general and beyond the consequences of concrete technologies or practices introduced by them. A great deal of work is being done on these topics, and although quite a few scholars predict disruptions, transformations, and even catastrophic shifts, the reactions of the academic community to these diagnoses are fairly bland. Initially they accepted digitalization as a reality, then harnessed all the fireworks – the concepts normally available to cultural studies and the social sciences – but disruptions and transformations were muted and routine forms of thinking took their place, along with the discovery of a new field of criticism, accompanied by the typically uncritical adoption of terms such as ‘artificial intelligence’, ‘data self-determination’, or ‘protection of privacy’.
The approach I take here is different. This book does not presuppose digitality and digitalization but asks why such a phenomenon could come into being, why it is obviously plausible for our society, in other words why it is not perceived as a disruption, and why it persists. Had it not suited this society, digitality would have never come into being or would have disappeared long ago. But, since it – whatever ‘it’ is – shows no tendency to vanish, it is worth asking, in a systematic manner, what problem is solved by digitalization. Hence I have not attempted to cram between these covers everything that I, or anyone, know or could hope to know about digitalization. The book should contain instead everything one needs to know in order to answer this question: what problem does digitalization solve?
The text is framed by two pictures by Vera Molnar, a Hungarian-born French artist who created art with the help of the computer as early as the late 1950s. This pioneer of computer art, now a nonagenerian, experimented early with digitalizing her hand drawings, for example of squares, and with calculating other shapes from them or expanding them via computer-controlled random generators. Her entire art is marked by the depiction of her fascination with patterns and by constant reference to patterns through their alienation or change, their variation and refraction. Two of her pictures are used here: at the beginning of the book, Hypertransformation, a plotter drawing from 1974; at the end, Aleatory Division of 4 Elements, from 1959, almost a parable of how patterns can emerge from very simple elements, strictly matched, as it were, through loosely matched recombinations. This will be one of the theses of the present book: how simple media generate complex forms. I thank Vera Molnar for granting me permission to use these images, which are about the same thing as the book itself: patterns and their variation range.
The book follows up on works from recent years. Although these hardly deal with matters of digitalization, they are in many respects preliminary research for this book. My thanks go to many participants in lectures and congresses where I had numerous opportunities to test the arguments presented here. Some critical questions helped in refining things. The same applies to those who attended my various lectures and seminars.
I have particularly benefitted, as always, from the very lively discussions at my chair in Munich. Most of all, the readings and critical comments from Gina Atzeni, Niklas Barth, Magdalena Göbl, and Julian Müller have been very helpful. I express my thanks to Till Ernstsohn and Christina Behler for help with my research. Christina Behler also contributed to proofreading and to compiling the index.
Irmhild Saake constantly shared with me her thoughts on the topic, and our long years of cooperation have left on this project more traces than can be seen. I cannot thank her enough.
I thank the C. H. Beck publishing house for their assistance with the publication of the German edition, in particular Matthias Hansl for editing.
Munich, Easter Monday, 2019
Armin Nassehi
I am very pleased that my theory of digital society, published in German by C. H. Beck Verlag, Munich, in 2019, is now being published in an English-language version.
My ambition was to fill a void, namely not only to make a sociological observation and analysis of digital technology, but to answer the question why digital technology is related fundamentally to the structure of modern society.
I am very grateful to Mirko Wittwar for translating the German text into English, to Polity Press for including the book in its programme, and especially to Manuela Tecusan for her thorough review of the English text. I would also like to thank my students Katharina Berger and Lukas Müller, who compiled the English-language material (translations and original versions) for the German-language quotations used in the German edition.
Without the generous support of the Fritz Thyssen Foundation, Cologne, this English-language edition would not have been possible.
Munich, November 2023
Armin Nassehi
This book presents a sociological theory of the digital society. If I were to see a book of this title, I would probably be sceptical – had I not written it myself. There is a long tradition of pinning societal diagnoses on one aspect only. Yet we know that in a risk society there is more than risk, that in an experience society action takes place too (if we pay heed to the distinction between action and experience), that even in an automobile society people sometimes fly or take the underground, that even in an accelerated society one must sometimes wait, and that even in a multi-option society there is often no choice. It has never really helped to define society by just one feature. In most cases this is only a makeshift solution or an attention grabber. In any event, tuning the diagnosis to a true feature makes things easier only at first sight; often it is not the authors themselves who invent such striking names, but those who understand a thing or two about how the economics of attention works in the book market.
This is now different. Of course, the society we live in is no digital society in the sense that everything happening within it can be explained by the digital nature of a kind of technology labelled ‘digital’. Nevertheless, in the course of the book I am going to claim that modern society is, in a way, digital even without digital technology, or that it can be understood only by applying digital means. I am going to go even further: I am going to claim that social modernity has always been digital, and hence that the digital technology is, after all, just the logical consequence of a society that is digital by its fundamental structure.
The first time I tested this idea was during the Hegel Lecture of 7 December 2017, at the Free University of Berlin.1 To understand digitalization – that cultural phenomenon that can be compared perhaps only with two other great inventions: the letterpress and the steam engine – we must not simply presuppose digitalization. Most discourses on digitalization always know already what it is about. In this book I would like to start by excluding this knowledge in order to answer the following crucial question:
What problem does digitalization solve?
The wording of this question is methodologically precise. It is a question about the function of digitalization. It does not define what digitality and digitalization are, but approaches the phenomenon by asking about the problem that digitalization is a societal solution for. So we are dealing with its societal function. Once this question has been answered, we are also going to unlock the technological dimensions of digitalization. If we do not want to talk about something that, after all, we know only through its user interface, we must begin with a methodically controlled question like this one.
If we look at discourses on the digital, it is conspicuous that they already presuppose the digital in a quite knowledgeable way. Either these are technological discourses that explain what the digital world can do – and then they clarify notions like search engine optimization, big data, augmented reality, or Internet of things as technological phenomena – or they slave away on the consequences of digitalization for labour markets, product markets, and attention markets; they diagnose shifts in the capitalist (re)production of value and of the concentration of economic power; and they venture prognoses of stronger or weaker disruption.2 Or else they focus on the practical everyday consequences of how digitalization affects its users.
Apart from a general thematic of anti-capitalist critique directed at the digitalized economy, scholars in social sciences, and especially in cultural studies, seem to be interested in a mixture of critical attitudes and descriptions of everyday life – which is, anyway, one of the most connectable forms of development and stabilization of topics, especially for sociology. It is not as if one could claim that the same thematic, let alone topical consensus, prevails everywhere, but obviously a sociological approach to digitalization is taking place under the keywords ‘subjectivation’, ‘self-techniques’, ‘optimization’, and ‘self-control’. The starting point, then, is that practices of self-tracking, for example, or of visual and textual presentation of one’s own self or control of it obey the rule of staging oneself. These approaches are thoroughly linked to the data processing of those traces that we leave behind through individual practices and that make us stage ourselves according to numerical practices, mostly metrical and comparative. It is particularly attractive to identify a neoliberal regime of technologies of the self that are designed to optimize the interface between self and world and to transform public control into self-control while concomitantly you become visible to public, official actors as well as to private market-based ones.
I would like to avail myself of some examples to explain these popular reflections on digitalization, based as they are on the social sciences – or rather cultural studies. More than twenty years ago Sherry Turkle had already raised the identity question, in light of the new ways of communicating on the Internet.3 Today Deborah Lupton’s Digital Sociology explores the significance of digitalization for sociology and takes up the challenge for sociology of a completely new way of accessing the data; but in the end she stumbles again upon its consequences for our way of life and our security.4Data Revolution, by Rob Kitchin, focuses mostly on data infrastructure and its political, organizational, and technological constitution.5 Shoshana Zuboff’s The Age of Surveillance Capitalism: The Fight for a Human Future at the New Frontier, a study rich in material, reflects above all on the control surplus that comes along with digital media.6 And Digital Societies, too, a volume edited by Jessie Daniels, Karen Gregory, and Tressie McMillan Cottom, focuses on the consequences of digitalization on specific aspects of the narrative.7 German counterparts such as Steffen Mau’s The Metric Society, with its wealth of informative material, take a similar line.8 There digitalization is presented as an aspect of behaviour that, after all, also works at the surplus of control. This holds even for technologically outstandingly informed works such as those by Dirk Helbing.9 Not even media theory works such as There Is No Software, by Friedrich Kittler,10 which has become almost a classic, or Sybille Krämer’s study Symbolische Maschinen11 perceive any of the social–structural radicality of the digital, according to which the place where we should look for a reference point for such culture-changing practices is the complexity of society; and neither do cultural studies’ dissociations from the technological infrastructure and its practices as ways of modelling, of collecting, imaging, and quantifying.12 To this series belongs also the very readable The Digital Condition, by Felix Stalder, which takes a media theory perspective.13
Such perspectives will not be denied at all – at least not yet, at this stage of elaboration, and not in principle. However, these are perspectives that ultimately take no interest in digitalization as such, but presuppose it as a technological, social, and cultural infrastructure. We should recall here, if only in passing, that in the pre-digital world western middle-class lifestyles were already characterized by various kinds of self-tracking, self-controlling behaviours, and disciplining. It looks as if many social sciences perspectives on digitalization do not let themselves be disturbed by digitalization itself. Rather they identify all other social aspects also as digitalization phenomena – from gender issues14 through inequality issues15 to the critique (already mentioned) of strategies of self-optimization.
Things are different with science and technology studies (STS). The French sociologist Dominique Cardon describes as simple-minded the disapproval of the power of algorithms that comes from interest-driven, especially economy-led critiques; and he does so on the grounds that ultimately they fail to see how the production of algorithms creates a new way of thinking. By referring to Gilbert Simondon, Cardon emphasizes that technology must be taken seriously on its own, if we want to be able to understand the algorithmization of social processes. Then the most criticized practices turn out to be secondary consequences rather than the starting point of the problem.16 This is the view I follow – but without restricting the enquiry to practices, as is commonly done in most STS works, mainly for ethnographic reasons. My motivation is shaped by the question of the social function of what is meant by digitalization.
Here it must be stated from the start that it is possible to ponder over issues of digitalization without considering digitalization itself, that is, without asking what it is that we are talking about when we speak of digitalization. Here I should point out that something similar occurs also in a different area: we think about society without asking what it is that we are talking about when we speak of society. I assume that these two conditions are systematically connected. Forgetting about society when talking about society runs parallel with forgetting about digitalization when talking about digitalization.
It is precisely this connection that I would like to unfold here, in systematic fashion, by which I mean explicitly sociologically; and this is no surprise, since making society our standard already introduces a sociological perspective. At any rate, I would like to emphasize, for starters, that I do not intend to ask the sociological question about digitalization just by way of presupposing ‘digitalization’ as an independent variable, only to answer, then, which other variables are affected by it.
This is not yet another contribution to the debate on the disruptions caused by digitalization and the practices supported by the digital infrastructure. Rather I would like to conceptualize the reference problem – the problem of the social reference of the digital. What I am interested in is why a technology that, quite obviously, was not designed for what it is currently doing was able to become so successful so extremely fast and ultimately to penetrate almost all parts of society. It will turn out that one of the success factors of this technology is indeed its technicity.
Structuring the problem around how digitalization affects, has affected, and will affect society would really make digitalization into an independent variable. I let myself be guided instead by a techno-sociological intuition: an idea that technology and society are not different entities, but that technologies and techniques can be successful only if they are compatible with the structure of a society. In other words, the fact that digitalization could be so successful – just like printing, the railway, the car, the radio, the nuclear bomb, or the technologization of medicine in earlier periods – is to be explained only by the structure of expectations – or rather the processing power – of the society in which it happens. To give just one example: the establishment of radio and of broadcasting technology already presupposes societies with potential listeners; it presupposes the idea of accessibility, as well as the appropriate centralist power structures of modern statehood. Radio and broadcasting technology requires a reservoir of what can be said; and it deals with the heterogeneity of a pluralist audience by assuming the homogeneity of addresses or addressees. It expects that what is spread via the radio will make a difference that attracts enough attention and – not least – motivates millions of people to buy a radio receiver. Mind you, the audience is not there yet, but there must be an amalgam of situations whose inner complexity makes something like an accessible audience not completely improbable. So the steam engine was not implemented only when its industrial conditions had come to exist: some accommodative conditions were already there. And the role the railway played in opening up North America gives a telling indication that technology can meet a demand that it itself creates, but that has requirements of its own.
It should be possible to provide evidence for something of this kind in the case of digitalization, too. Then the question will be: Which dispositions of modernity sensitize it to a technology such as digitalization (if anything like digitalization can be considered a reliable concept at all)? What is it about modernity, about socialmodernity, that was perhaps already ‘digital’, even before digitalization, to allow digital technology to start this triumphal procession, which actually is not in line with the intentions of its creators – just as the triumph of earlier technologies can never be explained as an intentional outcome either? The causal chain from idea to realization is too short-sighted, even if long causal chains are established.
This is not the place to lecture on the history and shallows of functionalism.17 Let me say just this: I am not dealing here with a set of clearly defined problems, to which we need to find solutions. The point is rather to understand better and determine both the problem and the solution. Concretely, I can define the problem that digitalization is a solution for only if I am aware of both solutions and problems – and, most of all, of how these two aspects relate to each other.
To repeat, one must extend considerably the functionalist frame of mind if one is to answer the question I have already indicated: What problem is digitalization meant to solve? And the question must be asked in such a way as to presuppose neither the problem nor the solution – so that there may be neither an existing list of problems nor an all-too-clear list of solutions for comparing the items to each other. A proper functionalist method must take both sides to be contingent; they must be of interest for the configuration itself. From a formal point of view, functionalism tells us that, if y is a function of x (y=f(x)), then both y and x must be taken to be contingent; and this rules out the possibility of taking one of them as an absolute value. This is exactly the problem that the critique of functionalism wrestles with.
For our topic, this means that, if the reference problem – that is, the problem–solution configuration of the digital – is to be determined, one must really start on both sides. If my initial intuition that technologies get implemented only if they are compatible with their social contexts is correct, this means that they solve a problem. So then, we should take both sides to be undetermined: what problem and what solution? By the way, solution means only that the process may go on, that compatibility has been created; hence it is not about what digitalization is, but about what it does and how it relates problem and solution.
This is exactly the beginning of the first chapter, which presents perhaps the most important thesis of the book: that digitalization is immediately related to the social structure. For this makes digitalization into a strange sort of disturbance – strange because it refers to the familiar with a radicalism that was not known previously. I am even going to claim that digitalization is not only a social phenomenon but a sociological project. Much of what digitalization does embodies a really sociological kind of thought: it makes use of social structures, it renders social dynamics visible, and out of these ways of recognizing patterns it creates added value. Of course, its actors are no sociological actors – they are enterprises and states, prosecuting authorities and media providers, communication agencies and the military, urban and social planning as well as the sciences. Yet what makes it sociological is that it recognizes or generates latent patterns and does something with them.
I am going to demonstrate that modern society was provided with a digital structure even before the use of digital computer technologies. What this means I am going to explain at a later stage. But the unmediated use of digital technology is a rather recent phenomenon. This piece of information probably makes a very modest contribution to knowledge, but, born as I was in 1960, I probably belong to one of the last promotions to have completed a university degree without any digital instruction. I passed my Abiturprüfung – my high school or baccalaureate exam – in Gelsenkirchen in 1979, to then study at the University of Münster, where I read educational sciences in parallel with philosophy, both with sociology as the secondary subject. I had to write a lot during my studies, as was (and still is) appropriate for university studies. Initially I had a mechanical typewriter from my parents, and working on it was pretty laborious. I think it was in my third semester, I don’t remember exactly when, that my studies received a first technological push. I bought a used Robotron 202, an electric typewriter made in East Germany by VEB Robotron Buchungsmaschinenwerk in Karl-Marx-Stadt. Calling this machine robust would be a blatant understatement. It was very heavy, the chassis extravagantly made of metal that was at least two millimetres thick. The engine of this machine had certainly not been developed for typewriters; you could command with it even more solid cultural goods than philosophical, educational, psychological, and sociological seminar papers. It was a very loud machine, which certainly shouldn’t come as a surprise. This held for both the engine and the typebars, which hit the paper and the platen roller with enormous power. I remember very well how the carriage return made the side table next to my desk sway. And I remember even more vividly how any keyboard mistake immediately affected what was written, corrections being almost impossible. This is what we call analogous technology – that is, a kind of technology designed for something like a one-on-one transfer of cause and effect, signal and reaction, control and implementation. Even corrections of mistakes with Tipp-Ex were always visible. The written text on the paper had healed, but the scars could be seen by everyone.
In 1985 I passed my examinations in educational sciences. For this purpose I had to write a thesis on sociology. It had about 350 pages – in those days we were still given that much time for our first qualification paper – handwritten to begin with, then copied out on my Robotron machine. Copying out meant giving it a form that was good enough for a professional office to make it into a paper that could be submitted. The master I had produced was not really bad but, in true analogous fashion, it contained all those irregularities, mistakes, and corrections that I had made during typing – indeed scars that bore testimony to the laborious process of tinkering with thoughts to make them into a text that could be read in a linear way. What was interesting was the office whose service I had employed: it advertised that, before the final printing, the client would be given a preliminary copy so that any remaining mistakes may be corrected, provided that the corrections did not alter the pagination. Technologically, this correction process was carried out on a very modern typewriter, which was very expensive – I could afford it only because my parents made a financial contribution. All of a sudden a printed text – that is, an analogous record of a one-on-one relation of production and product – not only became repeatable but could even be changed. And this change remained invisible! No scars! This had an effect on the reality status of the text, which suddenly was something else. What remained analogous was just the result, no longer the process of producing it.
After having completed my studies, I made efforts to be granted a PhD scholarship and imagined that in the future I would do precisely what I have been doing for three decades now: work as a sociologist and turn the results of this activity in particular into texts. All my studies (at least on the technological side of the means of production) could be conducted exclusively with analogous technology. Even the search for literature was still done without databases, with the help of a catalogue system whose materiality was similar to that of my Robotron machine. I still remember the sound at the university library in Münster when the box with the index cards was pushed back into the register – a veritable bang. By the way, taking the train to Bielefeld, which was about 100 kilometres away, was worth the effort in spite of the bad connection: Bielefeld had not only a much better stocked social science library but even a microfiche system that made research much easier. But even this feature was radically analogous – though at least it remained invisible without a device that consumed electricity.
Immediately after having completed my studies, my desired profession in mind, I started looking for an affordable computer that, unlike the very successful C64 Commodore computers, would not be for recreational use but would be a proper work tool. What I needed, then, was what even in those days was called ‘the industry standard’, namely a device compatible with the Microsoft Disc Operating System (MS-DOS), which was roughly equivalent in technology with the classic IBM PC. At the time, however, there was only one IBM branch in Münster; and a real IBM PC, as it was on the market since 1981, would have been completely unaffordable. For this reason one also had to go to Bielefeld, where some computer wizards were running a shop that offered reasonably priced components for an IBM-compatible computer like the first IBM PC – with an 8088 processor and 4.77 megacycles. My first device had no hard disc but just two floppy disk drives, one of which had always to be used with floppy disks for the operating system and the application programs. While the first disk was uploading the DOS, you inserted a floppy disk with a text-processing system; I was using Word Perfect then. When you wanted to use for the first time a special feature, for example italics, you had to insert another floppy disk, which supplied this tool. And when the text was finished you used another floppy disk, on which the finished document had to be stored.
This device had a dot matrix printer whose noise was in no way inferior to that of the Robotron machine. The whole device was expensive, although still cheaper than an IBM ball-head typewriter, which was the world-class standard at the time; hence it was something of a Cadillac by comparison with the Wartburg car represented by my Robotron. These ball-head typewriters were no longer the industrial standard but could be found in every university institute office, where they served a generation of professors who used to write almost everything by hand, because their text-processing program sat in front of the IBM typewriter and was not compatible with any kind of software, but with the idiosyncratic handwritings of the gentlemen professors (for once this is not a generic masculine!).
One year later I bought a hard disk – you could do this even in Münster those days – and faced the difficult choice between one with a capacity of 1 MB and one with a capacity of 5 MB. I opted for 1 MB because one could hardly imagine filling 5 MB of storage capacity in the course of a human life. From then on my digital biography was like everybody else’s: Windows appeared, then computers with greater capacity, more efficient peripheral devices, the Internet; my data became permanently accessible, no matter where I was. The transition from the download Internet to the upload Internet was very significant, then the transition from the stationary to the mobile Internet. With the Internet research possibilities emerged that made the Bielefeld microfiche period look antediluvial. And so on and so on. I wrote and completed this book (and earlier ones, too) in the form of files that were stored by the commercial cloud of a text-processing provider and that I was able to consult and edit to their current state on all my devices as well as on other people’s – from stationary computers to smartphones.
During my first semesters of studying, that is, between 1979 and 1981, when the first IBM PC appeared on the market – I made much money by repairing cars: the Volkswagen Beetle and the VW minibus, the Citroen 2CV and GX, the Renault 4 and 5, the Opel Kadett, the VW Polo and Golf I, and even the old Stroke 8 Mercedes diesel. That was as illegal as could be (though time-barred by now), because in those days cars were indeed analogous machines that could be tinkered together. For a little while cars were still devices that converted fossil into kinetic energy; but the processes were increasingly controlled, first through electric circuits and then through computer technology. Today I could at most change the tyres and the windscreen wipers on my automobile (a rather digitalized successor of the old Stroke 8). Consequently in 2001 the profession of car mechanic – probably the most desired apprenticeship, at least among boys – was renamed ‘mechatronics engineer’; the training profile had been changed even earlier.
What I’m getting at is probably clear by now: I, along with those born in the 1960s, can perhaps be described as the first digital generation.18 Indeed, the first PC was more than just some improved kind of typewriter. It was a medium that in fact changed the reality status of work results. In his famous 1936 essay ‘The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction’, Walter Benjamin supported the thesis that the experience of art had radically changed because it was possible to reproduce artistic exhibits: now the work of art had to prove its worth to a quite different kind of audience – and also to an audience no longer embedded in the bourgeois practices of enjoying art.19 The result was a sort of enjoyment of art en passant – which of course can be deplored only if the only thing one appreciates in art is its function of creating distinctiveness. But what mattered to Benjamin was what he called the ‘loss of aura’, that is, the loss of that cairological uniqueness that could extend into the chronological precisely through the repeatability of experience. Whoever quotes Benjamin certainly has in mind Adorno’s vitriolic accusation that Benjamin made the work of art into a fetish. But in my view this is a typical reaction to new kinds of media – be it Socrates’s praise of conversation in contrast to the distancing effect of writing, or the criticism of television as levelling things by comparison with real-world experience: an attempt to ennoble older forms with the help of semantics, in order to cope with the enormity of modern technology and its consequences.
The everyday use of digital technology has created something very similar – and, expressly, I am not talking here about the great cultural changes of the digital age, but about minor changes in the text production of a young scientist – or rather a youth who wanted to become a scientist. As a writing tool, the computer has not simply dematerialized writing. Before a text is brought to paper in the analogous way, it exists virtually. Its virtuality consists in remaining permanently open to change without having to change as a whole. Insertions, reformulations, revisions do not leave traces any longer; one would probably say, with Benjamin, that the text has lost its aura. Everything remains open to revision until the very end, and at the same time even preliminary versions seem aesthetically ready. Thanks to the functions of a text-processing software, absolutely incomplete texts could be presented all at once as if the text were indeed a text. One would not have done this in the past, on a Robotron 202, because that would have involved the considerable additional effort of rewriting everything all the time. Now, my concern in the present book is not to tell one of those popular stories about the impact of digitalization on everyday practices that make up the bulk of sociological literature on the topic. The example is intended only to show how digital technology is diffused into society – how small-scale it is and how suitable for daily use, how almost invisible yet effective, how unspectacular yet radical – and how swiftly the shift from an analog to a digital society has happened.
By itself, this book is not an immune reaction to digitalization, even if digitalization undoubtedly leads to disruptions of social routines that need our attention. I have already indicated what makes it interesting to social science scholars. Perhaps the most important discourse is the one about the future of work. It is highly likely that the digitalization of both production and products will have an impact on employment and on the continuity of professional biographies. But there is blatant disagreement on how digitalization will affect these issues. A lot is simply unknown. Also, there is little doubt that the accessibility of voluminous data sets will affect scientific insights. Fear of a theory-free science, which only looks for traces in data sets, looms everywhere;20 and there is the conundrum of whom to attribute knowledge to when intelligent algorithms conduct epistemic processes.21 It is definitely to be expected that there will be problems with adapting individual lifestyles to the mechanisms of control, by oneself or others, that will arise from the availability of growing masses of data. Likewise, there is little doubt that the pricing structure in many sectors will change as a result of completely new transparency and comparison models. Equally undisputed is a tendency towards the concentration of capital that runs parallel to the concentration of data.22 This is due to both economic and genuinely technological reasons. It is also certain that the debate on artificial intelligence will influence the self-understanding of human intelligence, which we label ‘natural’.23 And nobody will be able to ignore that new constellations and concentrations of power will appear along with digitalization.24 All this has been discussed for a long time: this is how society adjusts to such (self-imposed) disturbances. In this respect, digitalization is not really an exciting theme.
Although many of the topics mentioned here occur quite explicitly in the present book, they do not constitute the core of its content. To put it another way, they are not the starting point of my reflections, but feature only as epiphenomena of the actual object of investigation. For all these discussions about the disruption of social routines by an encroaching digital technology ultimately get by without any grounded theory of digitalization – they just presuppose digitalization as a phenomenon. This book will attempt to close this gap.
It may not be an exaggeration to claim that a gap is being filled here. The plan is no less than to present the first social theory of the digital society. This is a scholarly endeavour and not a superficially diagnostic one, let alone one that generates instructions for action. It is an attempt to understand digitalization as a social–cultural phenomenon.
Here digitalization is not simply applied to modern society as one topic among others. The theoretical claim is far more ambitious. For, according to my techno-sociological intuition, an appropriate theory of digitalization would not have to present a colonial or disruptive history of digitalization, but would have to be capable of identifying the reference problem of digitalization within society and its structure. In this respect, the subtitle has been chosen with great precision. We are dealing not with a theory of digitalization, but with a theory of digital society.
1
For a video recording of the Hegel Lecture, see
https://www.fu-berlin.de/en/sites/dhc/videothek/Videothek/948_Hegel_Lecture_mit_Armin_Nassehi/index.html
.
2
See e.g. Timo Daum,
Das Kapital sind Wir. Zur Kritik der Digitalen Ökonomie
, Hamburg: Edition Nautilus, 2017; Philipp Staab,
Falsche Versprechen: Wachstum im digitalen Kapitalismus
, Hamburg: Hamburger Edition, 2016; Yvonne Hofstetter,
Das Ende der Demokratie. Wie die künstliche Intelligenz die Politik übernimmt und uns entmündigt
, Munich: Penguin, 2018; Richard David Precht,
Jäger, Hirten, Kritiker: Eine Utopie für die digitale Gesellschaft
, Munich: Goldmann, 2018; Michael Betancourt,
The Critique of Digital Capitalism: An Analysis of the Political Economy of Digital Culture and Technology
, Santa Barbara, CA: Punctum Books, 2015.
3
Sherry Turkle,
Life on the Screen: Identity in the Age of the Internet
, New York: Simon & Schuster, 1997.
4
Deborah Lupton,
Digital Sociology
, New York: Routledge, 2015.
5
Rob Kitchin,
The Data Revolution: Big Data, Open Data, Data Infrastructures and Their Consequences
, London: SAGE, 2014.
6
Shoshana Zuboff,
The Age of Surveillance Capitalism: The Fight for a Human Future at the New Frontier of Power
, New York: PublicAffairs, 2019.
7
Jessie Daniels, Karen Gregory, and Tressie McMillan Cottom (eds),
Digital Sociologies
, Bristol: Policy Press, 2017.
8
Steffen Mau,
The Metric Society: On the Quantification of the Social
, Cambridge: Polity, 2019 (German edn 2017); see also Stefanie Duttweiler et al. (eds),
Leben nach Zahlen: Self-Tracking als Optimierungsprojekt?
Bielefeld: transcript, 2016; Zygmunt Bauman and David Lyon,
Liquid Surveillance: A Conversation
, Cambridge: Polity, 2012.
9
Dirk Helbig,
Towards Digital Enlightenment: Essays on the Dark and Light Sides of the Digital Revolution
, Cham: Springer, 2019.
10
Friedrich Kittler, ‘There Is No Software’, in Friedrich Kittler and Erik Butler (eds),
The Truth of the Technological World: Essays on the Genealogy of Presence
, Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 2014 (German edn 1993), pp. 219–29.
11
Sybille Krämer,
Symbolische Maschinen: Die Idee der Formalisierung im geschichtlichen Abriß
, Darmstadt: Wissenschaftliche Buchgesellschaft, 1988.
12
See Sybille Krämer and Horst Bredekamp (eds),
Bild, Schrift, Zahl
(2nd edn), Munich: Fink, 2009.
13
Felix Stalder,
The Digital Condition
, trans. by Valentine A. Pakis, Cambridge: Polity, 2018 (German edn 2016).
14
See e.g. Edelgard Kutzner and Victoria Schnier, ‘Geschlechterverhältnisse in Digitalisierungsprozessen von Arbeit: Konzeptionelle Überlegungen und empirische Fragestellungen’,
Arbeit
26 (2017), pp. 137–57.
15
See e.g. Klaus Dörre, ‘Digitalisierung: Neue Prosperität oder Vertiefung gesell- schaftlicher Spaltungen?’, in Hartmut Hirsch-Kreinsen, Peter Ittermann, and Jonathan Niehaus (eds),
Digitalisierung industrieller Arbeit
, Baden-Baden: Nomos, 2015, pp. 270–85; Paul DiMaggio et al., ‘Social Implications of the Internet’,
Annual Review of Sociology
27 (2001), pp. 307–36.
16
See Dominique Cardon, ‘Den Algorithmus dekonstruieren: Vier Typen digitaler Informationsberechnung’, in Robert Seyfert and Jonathan Roberge (eds),
Algorithmuskulturen: Über die rechnerische Konstruktion der Wirklichkeit
, Bielefeld: transcript, 2017, pp. 131–50; Dominique Cardon,
À quoi rêvent les algorithmes: Nos vies à l’heure des big data
, Paris: Seuil, 2015.
17
On this, see Armin Nassehi, ‘Rethinking functionalism: Zur Empiriefähigkeit systemtheoretischer Soziologie’, in Herbert Kalthoff (ed.),
Theoretische Empirie: Die Relevanz qualitativer Forschung
, Frankfurt: Suhrkamp, 2008, pp. 79–106.
18
On this, see Armin Nassehi, ‘Die erste digitale Generation: Eine kontraintuitive Diagnose’,
Kursbuch 178: 1964
, 2014, pp. 31–52.
19
Walter Benjamin,
The Work of Art in the Age of Mechanical Reproduction
, trans. by J. A. Underwood, London: Penguin, 2008.
20
Chris Anderson, ‘The End of Theory: The Data Deluge Makes the Scientific Method Obsolete’,
Wired
, 23 June 2008; Klaus Mainzer, ‘Zur Veränderung des Theoriebegriffs im Zeitalter von Big Data und effizienten Algorithmen’,
Berliner Debatte Initial
27.4 (2016), pp. 22–34.
21
Martina Franzen, ‘Die digitale Transformation der Wissenschaft’,
Beiträge zur Hochschulforschung
4.40 (2018), pp. 8–28.
http://www.bzh.bayern.de/uploads/media/4_2018_Franzen.pdf
.
22
See Nick Srnicek,
Platform Capitalism
, Cambridge: Polity, 2016.
23
For a particularly spectacular example, see Nick Bostrom,
Superintelligence: Paths, Dangers, Strategies
, Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2014.
24
Dirk Helbing,
Towards Digital Enlighenment: Essays on the Dark and Light Sides of the Digital Revolution
, Cham: Springer, 2019.
What problem does digitalization solve? If I am right, this question about the reference problem of digitalization has not yet been asked; and how you ask makes a difference. I do not ask, ‘What is digitalization?’ Nor do I ask, ‘What is the problem with digitalization?’, or ‘What problems does digitalization cause?’. Particularly about this last one, we sometimes know more than we do about my main question, on the reference problem. We know for example that digitalization is a threat to privacy, that it destroys jobs through its efficiency, especially in repetitive activities, that it can also be an economic opportunity, that it opens up possibilities of control that did not exist before, and so on. In a way, such statements presuppose digitalization as an independent variable, in order to enquire about its consequences. My question starts at a completely different point. What problem does it solve?
My answer is going to be as follows: the reference problem of digitalization is the complexity and, above all, the regularity of society itself. The argument is that modern society, especially through its digital kind of self-observation, encounters only those regularities, that stubbornness and resistance that make up social relations. True, society is a fluid, fast-moving, accelerated object, yet it is enormously stable, regular, and indeed predictable in many respects. This object contains patterns that are not recognizable at first sight. The second glance, which of course reveals them, is increasingly a digital one.
Should this thesis prove to be sustainable, it has considerable consequences for a sociological theory of digitalization that does not simply examine the consequences of digitalization and the manner of disruption attached to a certain kind of technology and technique but rather starts with the foundations of modern society itself. And this means that we do not see digitalization, but crucial parts of society are already seeing in digital fashion. Digitality is one of society’s crucial self-references. To be on the safe side, I should say right away that here I don’t take the digital as a metaphor. But more on this later.
This much is already clear: in the elaboration of a theory of digital society, methodological questions arise first, that is, questions of theory construction. If these are not answered, the few statements made so far remain simple assertions. The question about the reference problem is a functionalist one. Functionalist questions are not causal; they are about the relation between problem and solution.
Perhaps the most important foundation of functionalist thought comes from Ernst Cassirer. In his early book Substance and Function he postulated a transition from concepts of substance to concepts of function, thus presenting a critique not only of the ontological understanding of the world but also of the retrospective ontologization of the epistemic process. For Cassirer, epistemic objects are constituted in and by the cognitive process itself, which thereby becomes an undetermined point (or one to be determined) within a network of relations: ‘Thus we do not know “objects” as if they were already independently determined and given as objects – but we know objectively, by producing certain limitations and by fixating certain permanent elements and connections within the uniform flow of experience.’1
Cassirer calls the fact that cognition identifies ‘objects’ a ‘formula of confirmation’; and the identified objects are thus not so much ‘“signs of something objective” as rather objective signs’,2 whose objectivity is due to the fact that they prove their worth empirically.3
Then, from a mathematical perspective, the observation of something is always a function of this observation – and this conception of functionalism breaks with the idea that the indeterminacy of the world could be resolved or dissolved through unambiguous determinacy. This manner of relating is a feature not only of scientific insight but of practice in general. It makes visible how concrete decisions relate to something and how something appears the way it does as a result of a particular practice. Thus functionalism always has to do with indeterminacy, or, better still, with the practical production of determinacy – both on the side of cognition and on the side of the object.
Now this is not about epistemological questions around functionalism but actually about the question of the problem–solution constellation of what we call digitality or digitalization. So the thesis could be that we do not see the digital but that we see digitally, so that something like the digital may successfully become visible or emerge. One of the pioneers who do not just describe the digital but demonstrate how we should see digitally to describe the modern world is Dirk Helbing. This trained physicist describes for example the automatization of areas of society not as a mere disturbance that comes from the outside to a certain extent, but, on the contrary, as a part of the social structure that makes possible in the first place the description of disturbances such as the cascade effects in complex systems (e.g. energy supply).4 Consequently Helbing describes the digital revolution as a revolution of the complexity of society itself.
If a functionalist way of thinking is characterized by the need to keep both the cognition side and the object side contingent, it is worth starting with a phenomenological description of digital technologies. In other words, we must adopt an offline view to begin with and completely dispense with the description of the thing itself – that is, of digital technology – so as to get the fundamental structure of society into perspective. If there is anything that the entire digital shares, it is the capability of connecting data with data, that is, the capability of apparatuses to connect data points to one another. The raw material consists of data that exist in counted or countable form and whose form has such a low threshold that they can actually combine and recombine among themselves.
One of the earliest forms of digital – that is, countable – data processing was certainly government social statistics, which developed together with the establishment of the modern state. Thus the ‘social physicist’ Adolphe Quetelet (1796–1874) was one of the first to apply statistical methods to society and social planning. He wondered how much regularity is to be found in human behaviour, for example in marriage. Marital behaviour is in each case an individual kind of behaviour. Concretely, you are dealing with two people who decide to get married. But, numerically, what you are dealing with is slightly different. The piece of information ‘marriage’ recombines with other features, to then make visible what was not really visible before. Now, we must concede that even our everyday understanding works with probability assumptions concerning which marriage is to be expected and which is not. The idea of stratification in society, of cultural or denominational matching, of age distribution within couples, of economic and biographic preconditions, and so on is already rooted in our perceptual schemes and stereotypes, so that we recognize the regularity assumptions of our perceptions only in cases of deviation. But social statistics is able to conceptualize such regularities and ultimately to make them manageable; and through its quantitative capacity it is able to identify rather invisible regularities, which to everyday reasoning look like coincidences or like the contingent result of individual decision-makings.5
The prerequisite for all this is the form of data, a form that has become countable through the recoding of typical features, and a form of digital data, which can be recombined among themselves. Thus the material of data processing or digitality is items that in principle can be recombined among themselves and whose informational value consists precisely in the limited nature of possible combinations. More specifically, if any possible element were linked to any other possible element, the data could not provide any information at all, and so they could not make any difference. By the way, Quetelet regarded deviations from the normal distribution as a disturbance and ended up being fascinated by the idea of an homme moyen, an average person who can be calculated accordingly and who at the same time constitutes the foundation of all those practices through which humans are shaped as self-responsible individuals.
Thus the raw material of the digital consists in lists of coded numerical values, and the solution consists of information about everything that is possible on the basis of data. More specifically, these are probability statements about combinatorics, about how individual items are related – or, even more precisely, about the limits of combinatorics, because only data in which not everything combines with everything else can contain or generate information. This can be information of an entirely different nature:
the intelligent steering of a machine that is able to adjust itself to changing environmental conditions and to process data in such a way as to react to them through its own specifications;
the intelligent self-monitoring of mechanical machines through sensory data that indicate irregularities;
predictive possibilities of retrieving information on sales opportunities, narrowing down the suspects, or finding out about the recurrence of topics in a specific space, all from historical data on buying decisions, from deviant behaviour, or through search engine queries;
the optimization of logistic processing rules;
weather forecasts and climate models;
market monitoring and market development;
intelligent traffic control;
influencing voting behaviour in certain definable groups, or identifying uncertain decision-making situations in voting behaviour – for special promotional measures are worth using only there;
object recognition as a feature of self-driving vehicles;
diagnostic programs in medical imaging diagnostics;
assessments of electrocardiographic, electroencephalographic, and similar sets of data;
the forensic and literary analysis of textual authorship;
even the production of editorial texts through the processing of agency reports;
translation and speech recognition programs;
voice recognition;
the assessment of emotional states;
the detection of movement profiles of all kinds.
What all these examples have in common is that the interaction of different parameters is observed in terms of how the relation between different influencing variables changes as a result of the change in such relations, how high the probability is for certain desired or undesired states, or which influencing variables can change probabilities in a certain direction. If you want somehow to get to the heart of the digital, in the last resort it is nothing but a duplication of the world in the form of data, with the technological possibility of relating the data to one another, in order to retranslate this arrangement into specific questions. Comparability results from the fact that these signals are retranslated into a uniform medium, which makes the incommensurable at least relatable.
After all, this is already a precise definition of what a computer does. A computer is a computing machine capable of connecting the data through its own data management – that is, through meta-data – and of processing very large amounts of data thanks to its discrete – that is, binary – form of representing the ‘world’. Not only does this exceed the quantitative capacity of natural, consciousness-based intelligence, but a qualitative reversal also takes place, because the results of computations may again become prerequisites for new computations.
The connection between quantity and quality is indeed complex in this context, because it is precisely the quantitative nature of the feedback that lends the computer its particular quality. At any rate, digitality should be seen as a combination between simplification and enhanced complexity. One brings analog forms into digital shape, recombines this digital shape in terms of structures, and then applies these structures to the analog world whence the data come